Switch to: References

Citations of:

Le problème de l'Être chez Aristote

[author unknown]
Les Etudes Philosophiques 18 (1):77-77 (1963)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On the difficulty of understanding the sense of movement in Aristotle.Rafael Mello Barbosa - 2017 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 21:207-221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (3 other versions)Encrucijadas dialécticas: Elenchos, dispositivos antierísticos y Filosofia megárica en las refutaciones sofísticas.Claudia Mársico - 2015 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 14:137-148.
    Refutaciones Sofísticas ha sido usualmente interpretado como un intento de clasificación de sofismas. Este acercamiento, sin embargo, corre el riesgo de oscurecer la dimensión de sus propias intenciones confrontativas. El presente trabajo se propone enfatizar la importancia de las Refutaciones Sofísticas como parte de un programa antierístico que tiene por objetivo prioritario la filosofía megárica, en las antípodas de Aristóteles en el terreno epistemológico. Bajo esta luz, la resolución de argumentos erísticos excede el estudio lógico así como también la denuncia (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Il libro Epsilon della Metafisica di Aristotele nell’Epitome di Averroè.Carmela Baffioni - 2018 - Bulletin de Philosophie Medievale 59:33-56.
    This article deals with Averroes’s interpretation of Metaph. Ε 1, where Aristotle discusses the nature and object of metaphysics, as well as its place in the hierarchy of sciences. Among Averroes’s predecessors, al-Kindī seems to see a coincidence between metaphysics and theology, since God can be described as the “first cause of everything”. However, al-Fārābī and Avicenna discovered that “first philosophy” could be conceived as an ontology distinct from theology; moreover, they considered theology to be only a part of metaphysics, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle’s second problem about a science of being qua being.Vasilis Politis & Philipp Steinkrüger - 2017 - Ancient Philosophy 37 (1):59-89.
    It is commonly assumed that Aristotle thinks that his claim that being exhibits a category-based pros hen structure, which he introduces to obviate the problem of categorial heterogeneity, is sufficient to defend the possibility of a science of being qua being. We, on the contrary, argue that Aristotle thinks that the pros hen structure is necessary only, but not sufficient, for this task. The central thesis of our paper is that Aristotle, in what follows 1003b19, raises a second problem for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Une nouvelle histoire de la philosophie grecque.Yvon Lafrance - 1999 - Dialogue 38 (4):835-870.
    Philosophie grecqueest un ouvrage d'histoire de la philosophie du Vlesiècle av. J.-C. au XVesiècle byzantin et qui vient s'ajouter aux nombreuses histoires de la philosophie ancienne que nous a données l'historiographie française du xxesiècle. Le rythme de ces publications, même limitées à la tradition française, demeure impressionnant. En effet, une recherche rapide nous indiquerait facilement un rythme de publication d'environ une histoire de la philosophie ancienne tous les trois ans au cours de ce siècle. Une recherche plus poussée augmenterait sans (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phainomena e explicação na Ética Eudêmia de Aristóteles.Raphael Zillig - 2014 - In Zillig Raphael (ed.), Conocimiento, ética y estética en la Filosofía Antigua: Actas del II Simposio Nacional de Filosofía Antigua. Asociación Argentina de Filosofía Antigua. pp. 330-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Philosophy of Biomimicry.Henry Dicks - 2016 - Philosophy and Technology 29 (3):223-243.
    The philosophy of biomimicry, I argue, consists of four main areas of inquiry. The first, which has already been explored by Freya Mathews, concerns the “deep” question of what Nature ultimately is. The second, third, and fourth areas correspond to the three basic principles of biomimicry as laid out by Janine Benyus. “Nature as model” is the poetic principle of biomimicry, for it tells us how it is that things are to be “brought forth”. “Nature as measure” is the ethical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Self-Presupposition of the Origin: Homage to Cornelius Castoriadis.Ciaramelli Fabio - 1997 - Thesis Eleven 49 (1):45-67.
    Thinking the origin in a radical way amounts to thinking the movement by which what does not proceed from something else - what does not have its origin elsewhere - comes to itself, has within itself precisely the ontological energy to detach itself from itself and to exist as origin. In its primordial sense, then, origin is self-origin: it is, becomes, and is known starting from itself. This self-presupposition of the origin constitutes the very advent of Being, its unmotivated and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Une nouvelle histoire de la philosophie grecque.Yvon Lafrance - 1999 - Dialogue 38 (4):835-.
    Philosophie grecque est un ouvrage d'histoire de la philosophie du VIe siècle av. J.-C. au XVe siècle byzantin et qui vient s'ajouter aux nombreuses histoires de la philosophie ancienne que nous a données l'historiographie française du XXe siècle. Le rythme de ces publications, même limitées à la tradition française, demeure impressionnant. En effet, une recherche rapide nous indiquerait facilement un rythme de publication d'environ une histoire de la philosophie ancienne tous les trois ans au cours de ce siècleUne recherche plus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hegel's Ontological Grasp of Judgement and the Original Dividing of Identity into Difference.Jeffrey Reid - 2006 - Dialogue 45 (1):29-43.
    Within Hegel's system of science, judgement(Urteil)is thought's original dividing from identity into difference. In the same context, judgement is also an act of predication where “subject” must be understood in both a grammatical and psychical sense. Thus, judgement expresses a language act that is a self-positing into the difference of being. This article looks at two examples where Hegel's ontological notion of judgement obtains, then finds, the roots of this notion in Hölderlin and Fichte.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Facticity, necessity and contingency at Aristotle and Husserl.Irene Breuer - 2016 - HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology 5 (1):133-149.
    In his book Welt und Unendlichkeit, László Tengelyi has enquired into the possibility of a phenomenological metaphysics. Among the many issues addressed in his book, he thematized a real necessity of a non-apriori kind at Aristotle and Husserl, a necessity which he called „a necessity of the fact“. His research settled the basis for the present enquiry, which will examine the relationship between the absolute and the conditional necessity of a fact as well as the contingent or accidental features involved (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • El problema del tiempo en la física: un planteamiento existencial de la ciencia desde Heidegger.Felipe Johnson - 2016 - Arbor 192 (777):a294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Commentary on Kurt Pritzl: Aristotle on the conditions of thought.Victor Caston - 1998 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 14 (1):202-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Plato: Philosophy as Politics.Sorin Bocancea - 2009 - Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy 1 (1):155-180.
    One of the elements that obstruct the access to a presumed meaning of Plato’s doctrine is the use of the conventional meaning of the term “philosophia”, that is the signification that has prevailed after Aristotle. In order to eliminate this anachronism, it is necessary to review the meanings that the term had before Plato and in his dialogues. We should see that for the founder of the Academy philosophy was not a purely contemplative act, but one that was concerned with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • El inicio de la problemática ontológica en el comienzo de la filosofía.Inaki Marieta - 2014 - Isegoría 51:709-728.
    En el comienzo de la filosofía la problemática ontológica que hunde sus raíces en la propia lengua griega y más precisamente en el participio presente del verbo ser, va a cobrar una importancia decisiva para el desarrollo del pensamiento occidental. Esta marca lingüística, exclusiva de la lengua griega, justifica el hecho de que la filosofía sea función de la diferencia ontológica y que para aquella, ser y pensar sean lo mismo. Porque el ser sólo puede ser pensado desde la aprioridad (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Crítica de la figura de Protágoras en el Libro Γ de la Metafísica de Aristóteles.Diego Tabakian - 2017 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 53:373-410.
    En su defensa del Principio de no-contradicción, Aristóteles discute con varios interlocutores, desde los presocráticos hasta el sofista Protágoras, este último ampliamente conocido en la Antigüedad por trastocar el concepto de verdad con su doctrina del “homo mensura”, declarando así la imposibilidad del discurso falso. Consideramos que una lectura atenta del Libro Γ que rescate la figura del abderita puede mostrar cómo la crítica del sofista es clave para la constitución del pensamiento aristotélico en torno al problema de la verdad. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inheritance, Originality and the Will: Bergson and Heidegger on Creation.Mark Sinclair - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (5):655-675.
    In the work of Henri Bergson and Martin Heidegger we find different responses to traditional ideas of ‘creation’. Bergson advances a philosophy of creation, wherein ‘creation’ is presented as the production of a ‘radical’ or ‘absolute’ novelty, not only in art, but in all forms of human experience and biological life. Heidegger, in contrast, comes to criticise ideas of ‘creation’ in art as the expression of an alienated ‘humanism’ and ‘subjectivism’ essential to the modern age. This paper illuminates this divergence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Socrates' dream.Stanley Rosen - 1976 - Theoria 42 (1-3):161-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Multivocity in Topics 1.15.Mikołaj Domaradzki - 2016 - Peitho 7 (1):69-86.
    This paper discusses Aristotle’s account of multivocity as expounded in Topics 1.15. This article argues that an inquiry into how many ways something is said becomes for Aristotle a tool of dialectical examination that he employs throughout his entire philosophical career: investigating the many/multiple ways something is said allows one to recognize the ambiguity of the term in question and, consequently, to construct an adequate definition of its referent. The present study reconstructs the various strategies for detecting ambiguity and discusses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paul Ricoeur: metáfora e metafísica.Rosa Maria Filippozzi Martini - 2014 - Filosofia Unisinos 15 (3).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Le quattro cause della tragedia.Andrea Vestrucci - 2013 - Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy 5 (1):150-178.
    This paper aims to analyze one of the highest achievements of humankind, the classical tragedy, via the application of the heuristic paradigm proposed by Aristotle in his Physics, the fourfold determination of the concept of cause. This scientific methodology – one of the most effective viatica for a comprehensive response to the question of the nature of an object – informs the inquiry into the universal nature of tragedy, its hypercomplexity and hence its ethical and human relevance. Firstly, the concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ce qui se trouve là et ce qui est fait. Le nom de l’être et la réception d’Aristote dans la falsafa.Kristell Trego - 2017 - Quaestio 17:111-131.
    In his Kitab al-ḥuruf, al-Fârâbî exposed a problem: Arabic language doesn’t have a word corresponding to the Greek verb einai. This paper examines the way Arabic philosophers managed to practice me...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dialéctica, diaporetica y saber positivo en la metafísica de Aristóteles.Aguirre Javier - 2010 - Endoxa 26:11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Le statut de l'argument dialectique d'après. Réf soph. 11, 172a9–15.Louis-André Dorion - 1990 - Dialogue 29 (1):95-.
    La détermination du statut de la dialectique aristotélicienne aura certes été l'une des principales tâches auxquelles se seront consacrés les chercheurs de cette seconde moitié du siècle. Le nombre d'études qui traitent de cette question est en effet considérable. Or en dépit de tous ces travaux, l'interprétation de certains passages, où Aristote traite expressément du statut de la dialectique, demeure controversée. C'est entre autres le cas d'un court passage du chapitre 11 desRéfutations sophistiques(=RS), chapitre à propos duquel É. Weil a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Husserl und die kritische Rehabilitierung der aristotelischen Ontologie.Irene Breuer - 2019 - Husserl Studies 35 (3):203-224.
    Die Phänomenologie Husserls ist nicht nur als ein metaphysikkritisches Unternehmen, sondern als eine kritische Wiederaufnahme aristotelischer Themen aufzufassen. Denn die Frage nach dem Sinn des Seins führt Husserl anfänglich dazu, eine transzendentale Phänomenologie als eidetische Wissenschaft zu entwerfen, welche die aristotelische Ontologie auf formale und materiale Regionen erweitert. Später aber führt sie Husserl nicht nur zu einer Revision der Beziehungen zwischen Phänomenologie und Metaphysik, sondern zu einer Erweiterung des phänomenologischen Bereiches auf Fragen der letzten absolut gegebenen Urtatsachen, die eine phänomenologische (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)"Compreensão do ser" como barreira ao outro?: Lévinas, ser e tempo e o segundo Heidegger.Rodrigo Guerizoli - 2005 - Natureza Humana 7 (1):159-177.
    No núcleo da leitura efetuada por Emmanuel Lévinas do projeto de uma "ontologia fundamental", concretizado por Martin Heidegger em Ser e Tempo , encontramos uma severa crítica à noção de "compreensão do ser". Lévinas não considera essa expressão senão o solo de uma filosofia sobremaneira incapaz de dimensionar a questão do outro. O objetivo deste artigo é, com base em reflexões de Heidegger acerca da expressão "sentido do ser" - reunidas em diversas passagens de seus Contributos à filosofia -, analisar (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark