Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A robust resolution of Newcomb’s paradox.Thomas A. Weber - 2016 - Theory and Decision 81 (3):339-356.
    Newcomb’s problem is viewed as a dynamic game with an agent and a superior being as players. Depending on whether or not a risk-neutral agent’s confidence in the superior being, as measured by a subjective probability assigned to the move order, exceeds a threshold or not, one obtains the one-box outcome or the two-box outcome, respectively. The findings are extended to an agent with arbitrary increasing utility, featuring in general two thresholds. All solutions require only minimal assumptions about the being’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Causal Decision Theory and the Fixity of the Past.Arif Ahmed - 2014 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65 (4):665-685.
    Causal decision theory (CDT) cares only about the effects of a contemplated act, not its causes. The article constructs a case in which CDT consequently recommends a bet that the agent is certain to lose, rather than a bet that she is certain to win. CDT is plainly giving wrong advice in this case. It therefore stands refuted. 1 The Argument2 The Argument in More Detail2.1 The betting mechanism2.2 Soft determinism2.3 The content of P 2.4 The argument again3 The Descriptive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The lesson of Newcomb’s paradox.David H. Wolpert & Gregory Benford - 2013 - Synthese 190 (9):1637-1646.
    In Newcomb’s paradox you can choose to receive either the contents of a particular closed box, or the contents of both that closed box and another one. Before you choose though, an antagonist uses a prediction algorithm to accurately deduce your choice, and uses that deduction to fill the two boxes. The way they do this guarantees that you made the wrong choice. Newcomb’s paradox is that game theory’s expected utility and dominance principles appear to provide conflicting recommendations for what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Newcomb’s Many Problems.Isaac Levi - 1975 - Theory and Decision 6 (2):161-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Newcomb’s Paradox and the Direction of Causation.John L. Mackie - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (2):213 - 225.
    Newcomb's paradox was first presented by Robert Nozick and has been discussed by a considerable number of writers. You are playing a game with a Being who seems to have extraordinary predictive powers. Before you are two boxes, in one of which you can see $1,000. The other is closed and you cannot see what it contains, but you know that the Being has put a million dollars into it if he has predicted that you will take it only, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Newcomb’s Problem and Repeated Prisoners’ Dilemmas.Christoph Schmidt-Petri - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):1160-1173.
    I present a game-theoretic way to understand the situation describing Newcomb’s Problem (NP) which helps to explain the intuition of both one-boxers and two-boxers. David Lewis has shown that the NP may be modelled as a Prisoners Dilemma game (PD) in which ‘cooperating’ corresponds to ‘taking one box’. Adopting relevant results from game theory, this means that one should take just one box if the NP is repeated an indefinite number of times, but both boxes if it is a one-shot (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ratificationism without ratification: Jeffrey meets Savage.Wlodzimierz Rabinowicz - 1985 - Theory and Decision 19 (2):171-200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Newcomb University: A play in one act.Adam Elga - 2020 - Analysis 80 (2):212-221.
    Counter-intuitive consequences of both causal decision theory and evidential decision theory are dramatized. Each of those theories is thereby put under some pressure to supply an error theory to explain away intuitions that seem to favour the other. Because trouble is stirred up for both sides, complacency about Newcomb’s problem is discouraged.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Real Reason Why the Prisoner’s Dilemma is Not a Newcomb Problem.Mark Thomas Walker - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (3):841-859.
    It is commonly thought, in line with the position defended in an influential paper by David Lewis, that the decision problems faced in the prisoner’s dilemma and the Newcomb situation are essentially the same problem. José Luis Bermúdez has recently attacked the case Lewis makes for this claim. While I think the claim is false, I contend that Bermúdez’s reason for rejecting Lewis’s argument is inadequate, and then outline what I take to be a better reason for doing so.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Newcomb's paradox and omniscience.R. Lance Factor - 1978 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9 (1):30 - 40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Newcomb's many problems.Isaac Levi - 1978 - In A. Hooker, J. J. Leach & E. F. McClennen (eds.), Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory: Vol.II: Epistemic and Social Applications. D. Reidel. pp. 369--383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The unpredictability of free choices.G. Schlesinger - 1974 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25 (3):209-221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Divine foreknowledge and newcomb's paradox.William Lane Craig - 1987 - Philosophia 17 (3):331-350.
    Newcomb's Paradox thus serves as an illustrative vindication of the compatibility of divine foreknowledge and human freedom. A proper understanding of the counterfactual conditionals involved enables us to see that the pastness of God's knowledge serves neither to make God's beliefs counterfactually closed nor to rob us of genuine freedom. It is evident that our decisions determine God's past beliefs about those decisions and do so without invoking an objectionable backward causation. It is also clear that in the context of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Psychological determinism and rationality.Ruth Weintraub - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (1):67-79.
    There are arguments which purport to rebut psychological determinism by appealing to its alleged incompatibility with rationality. I argue that they all fail. Against Davidson, I argue that rationality does not preclude the existence of psychological laws. Against Popper, I argue that rationality is compatible with the possibility of predicting human actions. Against Schlesinger, I claim that Newcomb's problem cannot be invoked to show that human actions are unpredictable. Having vindicated the possibility of a rationally-based theory of action, I consider (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Newcomb's paradox: A realist resolution.N. Jacobi - 1993 - Theory and Decision 35 (1):1-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Nice Soft Facts’: Fischer on Foreknowledge.William Lane Craig - 1989 - Religious Studies 25 (2):235 - 246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Gideon's paradox — a paradox of rationality.Maya Bar-Hillel & Avishai Margalit - 1985 - Synthese 63 (2):139 - 155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Newcomb's paradox and compatibilism.Yemima Ben-Menahem - 1986 - Erkenntnis 25 (2):197 - 220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-reference and the acyclicity of rational choice.Haim Gaifman - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 96 (1-3):117-140.
    Self-reference in semantics, which leads to well-known paradoxes, is a thoroughly researched subject. The phenomenon can appear also in decision theoretic situations. There is a structural analogy between the two and, more interestingly, an analogy between principles concerning truth and those concerning rationality. The former can serve as a guide for clarifying the latter. Both the analogies and the disanalogies are illuminating.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Schlesinger on the newcomb problem.James L. Hudson - 1979 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57 (2):145 – 156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark