Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Bons Procédés Entre Érudits.Samuel Gessner - 2010 - Revue de Synthèse 131 (4):523-541.
    Cet article met en évidence certaines fonctions de la correspondance scientifique dans la deuxième moitié du XVIe siècle. Un professeur de mathématiques à Rome, Antonio Maria Pazzi, envoie un mésolabe à Barbara, humaniste érudit de Venise, accompagné d’une lettre. Barbara l’inclut dans la version latine de son commentaire à Vitruve. L’analyse du contexte de cette publication montre que tous deux font coïncider leurs intentions personnelles et l’idéal du« bien commun», en contribuant à la diffusion de connaissances et de pratiques mathématiques.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Early modern mathematical practice in the round. [REVIEW]Richard J. Oosterhoff - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (1):224-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Hunting the White Elephant: When and How did Galileo Discover the Law of Fall?Jürgen Renn, Peter Damerow, Simone Rieger & Domenico Giulini - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (s1):29-149.
    we present a number of findings concerning galileo's major discoveries which question both the methods and the results of dating his achievements by common historiographic criteria. the dating of galileo's discoveries is, however, not our primary concern. this paper is intended to contribute to a critical reexamination of the notion of discovery from the point of view of historical epistemology. we claim that the puzzling course of galileo's discoveries is not an exceptional comedy of errors but rather illustrates the normal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • “A Plague to the Learned World”: Pieter Gabry, F.R.S. (1715–1770) and His Use of Natural Philosophy to Gain Prestige and Social Status. [REVIEW]Huib J. Zuidervaart - 2007 - History of Science 45 (3):287-326.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the frontlines of the scientific revolution: How mersenne learned to love Galileo.Daniel Garber - 2004 - Perspectives on Science 12 (2):135-163.
    : Marin Mersenne was central to the new mathematical approach to nature in Paris in the 1630s and 1640s. Intellectually, he was one of the most enthusiastic practitioners of that program, and published a number of influential books in those important decades. But Mersenne started his career in a rather different way. In the early 1620s, Mersenne was known in Paris primarily as a writer on religious topics, and a staunch defender of Aristotle against attacks by those who would replace (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The social life of precision instruments: artisans’ trials in early-modern England, 1550–1700.Boris Jardine - 2024 - Annals of Science 81 (1):100-123.
    This paper examines the role of mathematical instrument makers in establishing a public culture of precision measurement in early-modern England. I argue that this culture was promoted through trials and demonstrations, in the context of which artisans held a privileged position. The trials described here cover land surveying, the measurement of magnetic variation, and standards of measurement for customs and excise. These trials were decisive moments in the ‘cultural biographies’ of precision instruments. I ask how it was that instrument makers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A learned artisan debates the system of the world: Le Clerc versus Mallemant de Messange.Oded Rabinovitch - 2017 - British Journal for the History of Science 50 (4):603-636.
    Sébastien Le Clerc (1637–1714) was the most renowned engraver of Louis XIV's France. For the history of scientific publishing, however, Le Clerc represents a telling paradox. Even though he followed a traditional route based on classic artisanal training, he also published extensively on scientific topics such as cosmology and mathematics. While contemporary scholarship usually stresses the importance of artisanal writing as a direct expression of artisanal experience and know-how, Le Clerc's publications, and specifically the work on cosmology in hisSystème du (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Newton and scholastic philosophy.Dmitri Levitin - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Science 49 (1):53-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Familiar Demonstrations in Geometry”: French and Italian Engineers and Euclid in the Sixteenth Century.Pascal Brioist - 2009 - History of Science 47 (1):1-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Clavius, Proclus, and the Limits of Interpretation: Snapshot-idealization versus Projectionism.Guy Claessens - 2009 - History of Science 47 (3):317-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Inside the Kunstkammer: the circulation of optical knowledge and instruments at the Dresden Court.Sven Dupré & Michael Korey - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (4):405-420.
    The Kunstkammer of the Electors of Saxony, founded in Dresden around 1560, housed one of the richest collections of tools and scientific instruments in its day. A close analysis of the optical objects in the collection in the decades around 1600 is undertaken here—in particular, their arrangement by a mathematically trained curator, Lucas Brunn, and their use in an ‘experiment’ by a distinguished visitor, Johannes Kepler. It is argued that the selection, display and use of optical objects within this collection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Meanings and contexts: Mr Skinner's Hobbes and the English mode of political theory.Ted Miller & Tracy B. Strong - 1997 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 40 (3):323 – 355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sir John Colbatch and Augustan medicine: Experimentalism, character and entrepreneurialism.Harold J. Cook - 1990 - Annals of Science 47 (5):475-505.
    SummaryThe medical career of Sir John Colbatch illuminates some of the ways in which experimental philosophy, social change, and medical entrepreneurialism together helped bring about the end of the old medical regime in England. Colbatch's career in Augustan England depended very much on a growing public culture in which the well-to-do decided matters of intellectual importance for themselves, becoming increasingly free not only from the clerics but from the physicians. In this new world, debates about the fundamental principles of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mathématiques et arts de penser depuis le XVe siècle.Giovanna Cifoletti & Jean-Marie Coquard - 2022 - Revue de Synthèse 143 (3-4):213-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Milliet Dechales as Historian of Mathematics.Antoni Malet - 2022 - Perspectives on Science 30 (3):463-492.
    The Jesuit C.F. Milliet Dechales, author of one of the most famous early modern mathematical encyclopedias, Cursus seu mundus mathematicus, wrote a hundred-folio-page long treatise devoted to the “progress of mathematics,” which was published in the second, enlarged edition of his encyclopedia. His historical treatise covers the gamut of mixed mathematics—including astronomy, mechanics, optics, music, geography and navigation, ars tignaria, and architecture. The early modern historical narratives about the mathematical sciences, from Regiomontanus’s Oratio onwards, have been aptly characterized by their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Hunting the White Elephant: When and How did Galileo Discover the Law of Fall?Jürgen Renn, Peter Damerow, Simone Rieger & Domenico Giulini - 2000 - Science in Context 13 (3-4):299-419.
    The ArgumentWe present a number of findings concerning Galileo's major discoveries which question both the methods and the results of dating his achievements by common historiographic criteria. The dating of Galileo's discoveries is, however, not our primary concern. This paper is intended to contribute to a critical reexamination of the notion of discovery from the point of view of historical epistemology. We claim that the puzzling course of Galileo's discoveries is not an exceptional comedy of errors but rather illustrates the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Tartaglia's ragioni: A maestro d'abaco's mixed approach to the bombardier's problem.Karin J. Ekholm - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Science 43 (2):181-207.
    In La nova scientia , Niccolò Tartaglia analyses trajectories of cannonballs by means of different forms of reasoning, including ‘physical and geometrical reasoning’, ‘demonstrative geometrical reasoning’, ‘Archimedean reasoning’, and ‘algebraic reasoning’. I consider what he understood by each of these methods and how he used them to render the quick succession of a projectile's positions into a single entity that he could explore and explain. I argue that our understanding of his methods and style is greatly enriched by considering the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “The Mind Is Its Own Place”: Science and Solitude in Seventeenth-Century England.Steven Shapin - 1991 - Science in Context 4 (1):191-218.
    The ArgumentIt is not easy to point to the place of knowledge in our culture. More precisely, it is difficult to locate the production of our most valued forms of knowledge, including those of religion, literature and science. A pervasive topos in Western culture, from the Greeks onward, stipulates that the most authentic intellectual agents are the most solitary. The place of knowledge is nowhere in particular and anywhere at all. I sketch some uses of the theme of the solitary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The anthropology of incommensurability.Mario Biagioli - 1990 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 21 (2):183-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)Working Knowledges Before and After circa 1800.John V. Pickstone - 2007 - Isis 98 (3):489-516.
    ABSTRACT Historians of science, inasmuch as they are concerned with knowledges and practices rather than institutions, have tended of late to focus on case studies of common processes such as experiment and publication. In so doing, they tend to treat science as a single category, with various local instantiations. Or, alternatively, they relate cases to their specific local contexts. In neither approach do the cases or their contexts build easily into broader histories, reconstructing changing knowledge practices across time and space. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ideology, Inevitability, and the Scientific Revolution.John Henry - 2008 - Isis 99 (3):552-559.
    ABSTRACT Looking in particular at the Scientific Revolution, this essay argues that, for all their differences, positivist commentators on science and contextualist historians of science ought to be committed to the view that counterfactual changes in the history of science would have made no significant difference to its historical development. Assumptions about the history of science as an inexorable march toward the truth commit the positivist to the view that, even if things had been different, scientific knowledge would still have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • ‘Mathematics Made No Contribution to the Public Weal’: Why Jean Fernel (1497-1558) Became a Physician.John Henry - 2011 - Centaurus 53 (3):193-220.
    This paper offers a caution that emphasis upon the importance of mathematics in recent historiography is in danger of obscuring the historical fact that, for the most part, mathematics was not seen as important in the pre-modern period. The paper proceeds by following a single case study, and in so doing offers the first account of the mathematical writings of Jean Fernel (1497–1558), better known as a leading medical innovator of the 16th century. After establishing Fernel's early commitment to mathematics, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Practical mathematicians and mathematical practice in later seventeenth-century London.Philip Beeley - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Science 52 (2):225-248.
    Mathematical practitioners in seventeenth-century London formed a cohesive knowledge community that intersected closely with instrument-makers, printers and booksellers. Many wrote books for an increasingly numerate metropolitan market on topics covering a wide range of mathematical disciplines, ranging from algebra to arithmetic, from merchants’ accounts to the art of surveying. They were also teachers of mathematics like John Kersey or Euclid Speidell who would use their own rooms or the premises of instrument-makers for instruction. There was a high degree of interdependency (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alessandro Piccolomini and the certitude of mathematics.Daniele Cozzoli - 2007 - History and Philosophy of Logic 28 (2):151-171.
    This paper offers a reconstruction of Alessandro Piccolomini's philosophy of mathematics, and reconstructs the role of Themistius and Averroes in the Renaissance debate on Aristotle's theory of proof. It also describes the interpretative context within which Piccolomini was working in order to show that he was not an isolated figure, but rather that he was fully involved in the debate on mathematics and physics of Italian Aristotelians of his time. The ideas of Lodovico Boccadiferro and Sperone Speroni will be analysed. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Adriaan van Roomen y la uranografía: el enlace de las disciplinas matemáticas y de la filosofía en los siglos XVI y XVII.Zaqueu Vieira Oliveira - 2018 - Metatheoria – Revista de Filosofía E Historia de la Ciencia 9:13--28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Transformation of Aristotle's Mechanical Questions: A Bridge Between the Italian Renaissance Architects and Galileo's First New Science.Matteo Valleriani - 2009 - Annals of Science 66 (2):183-208.
    Summary The reception process of Aristotle's Mechanical Questions during the early modern period began with the publication of the corpus aristotelicum between 1495 and 1498. Between 1581 and 1627, two of the thirty-five arguments discussed in the text, namely Question XIV concerning the resistance to fracture and Question XVI concerning the deformation of objects such as timbers, became central to the work of the commentators. The commentaries of Bernardino Baldi (1581–1582), Giovanni de Benedetti (1585), Giuseppe Biancani (1615) and Giovanni di (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wie Huren und Betrüger — die Begegnung des jungen Descartes mit der Welt der Praktiker der Mathematik.Ivo Schneider - 1997 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 20 (2-3):173-188.
    Descartes describes in the Discours de la méthode his stay in Germany in winter 1619/20 as decisive for his intellectual development. In Germany he was especially interested in the mathematics of German reckoningmasters and mathematical practitioners. Frustrated from their form of representation, from their mathematical „style”, he began to create his own, which he considered a first step in the development of his method in order to secure true knowledge. Descartes could derive additional confirmation for his task by the mentalities (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation