Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Galileo Galilei and the centers of gravity of solids: a reconstruction based on a newly discovered version of the conical frustum contained in manuscript UCLA 170/624.Riccardo Bellé & Beatrice Sisana - 2022 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 76 (5):471-511.
    The manuscript UCLA 170/624 contains Galileo’s proof of the center of gravity of the frustum of a cone, which was ultimately published as Theoremata circa centrum gravitatis solidorum in Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche intorno a due nuove scienze. The UCLA copy opens the possibility of giving a fuller account of Theoremata dating and development, and it can shed light on the origins of this research by the young Galileo. A comparison of the UCLA manuscript with the other extant copies is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Honesty Still Is the Best Policy.Joseph Agassi - 2014 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (5):673-687.
    Fuller describes the place of intellectuals in the modern world—as researchers, teachers, academics, and citizens. Their job is that of developing and promoting ideas. He explains their failure to perform well and offers advice: say what you think you should say, not necessarily what you think. The advice is unsuitable; it is aimed at advisers and expert witnesses, not at intellectuals. Also, his analysis invites proposals for social reforms aimed at lowering traditional expectations of intellectuals and toward presenting them with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Paradox of Conceptual Novelty and Galileo’s Use of Experiments.Maarten Van Dyck - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):864-875.
    Starting with a discussion of what I call Koyré’s paradox of conceptual novelty, I introduce the ideas of Damerow et al. on the establishment of classical mechanics in Galileo’s work. I then argue that although the view of Damerow et al. on the nature of Galileo’s conceptual innovation is convincing, it misses an essential element: Galileo’s use of the experiments described in the first day of the Two New Sciences. I describe these experiments and analyze their function. Central to my (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hoe Galileo Galilei de valwet ontdekte, en het verschil dat dit maakt.Maarten Van Dyck - 2021 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 113 (1):81-105.
    How Galileo Galilei discovered the law of fall, and the difference that this makes Galileo’s law of fall is one of the crucial building blocks of classical mechanics. The question how this law was discovered has often been a topic of debate. This article offers a reconstruction of the developments within Galileo’s research that led to the discovery of the law. This reconstruction is offered to make a philosophical point regarding the epistemic status of experimental results: Galileo’s experiments can offer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Jochen Büttner, Swinging and Rolling: Unveiling Galileo's Unorthodox Path from a Challenging Problem to a New Science, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer, 2019. [REVIEW]Maarten Van Dyck - 2022 - Centaurus 64 (4):925-940.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Medieval Representations of Change and Their Early Modern Application.Matthias Schemmel - 2014 - Foundations of Science 19 (1):11-34.
    The article investigates the role of symbolic means of knowledge representation in concept development using the historical example of medieval diagrams of change employed in early modern work on the motion of fall. The parallel cases of Galileo Galilei, Thomas Harriot, and René Descartes and Isaac Beeckman are discussed. It is argued that the similarities concerning the achievements as well as the shortcomings of their respective work on the motion of fall can to a large extent be attributed to their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From the History of Science to the History of Knowledge - and Back.Jürgen Renn - 2015 - Centaurus 57 (1):37-53.
    The history of science can be better understood against the background of a history of knowledge comprising not only theoretical but also intuitive and practical knowledge. This widening of scope necessitates a more concise definition of the concept of knowledge, relating its cognitive to its material and social dimensions. The history of knowledge comprises the history of institutions in which knowledge is produced and transmitted. This is an essential but hitherto neglected aspect of cultural evolution. Taking this aspect into account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A New Look at Galileo's Search for Mathematical Proofs.P. Palmieri - 2006 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 60 (3):285-317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Paolo Sarpi and the first Copernican tidal theory.Ron Naylor - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Science 47 (4):661-675.
    Despite his demanding religious responsibilities, Paolo Sarpi maintained an active involvement in science between 1578 and 1598 – as hisPensierireveal. They show that from 1585 onwards he studied the Copernican theory and recorded arguments in its favour. The fact that for 1595 they include an outline of a Copernican tidal theory resembling Galileo'sDialoguetheory is well known. But examined closely, Sarpi's theory is found to be different from that of theDialoguein several important respects. That Sarpi was a Copernican by 1592 is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Galileo's scientific discoveries, cosmological confrontations, and the aftermath.Stephen Mason - 2002 - History of Science 40 (130):377-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nature’s drawing: problems and resolutions in the mathematization of motion.Ofer Gal & Raz Chen-Morris - 2012 - Synthese 185 (3):429-466.
    The mathematical nature of modern science is an outcome of a contingent historical process, whose most critical stages occurred in the seventeenth century. ‘The mathematization of nature’ (Koyré 1957 , From the closed world to the infinite universe , 5) is commonly hailed as the great achievement of the ‘scientific revolution’, but for the agents affecting this development it was not a clear insight into the structure of the universe or into the proper way of studying it. Rather, it was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Idealization and Galileo’s Proto-Inertial Principle.Maarten Van Dyck - 2018 - Philosophy of Science 85 (5):919-929.
    Galileo proposed what has been called a proto-inertial principle, according to which a body un horizontal motion will conserve its motion. This statement is only true in counterfactual circumstances where no impediments are present. This paper analyzes how Galileo could have been justified in ascribing definite properties to this idealized motion. This analysis is then used to better understand the relation of Galileo’s proto-inertial principle to the classical inertial principle.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Del Monte, Guidobaldo.Maarten Van Dyck - 2019 - Encylopedia of Renaissance Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Experimento E Matemática Na Lei Da Queda Dos Corpos De Galileu Galilei.Márcio Correia dos Santos - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Campinas (Unicamp)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark