Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A reconstruction of Aristotle's modal syllogistic.Marko Malink - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (2):95-141.
    Ever since ?ukasiewicz, it has been opinio communis that Aristotle's modal syllogistic is incomprehensible due to its many faults and inconsistencies, and that there is no hope of finding a single consistent formal model for it. The aim of this paper is to disprove these claims by giving such a model. My main points shall be, first, that Aristotle's syllogistic is a pure term logic that does not recognize an extra syntactic category of individual symbols besides syllogistic terms and, second, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Dialectical Contradictions and Classical Formal Logic.Inoue Kazumi - 2014 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 28 (2):113-132.
    A dialectical contradiction can be appropriately described within the framework of classical formal logic. It is in harmony with the law of noncontradiction. According to our definition, two theories make up a dialectical contradiction if each of them is consistent and their union is inconsistent. It can happen that each of these two theories has an intended model. Plenty of examples are to be found in the history of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frege plagiarized the Stoics.Susanne Bobzien - 2021 - In Fiona Leigh (ed.), Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy, Keeling Lectures 2011-2018, OPEN ACCESS. University of Chicago Press. pp. 149-206.
    In this extended essay, I argue that Frege plagiarized the Stoics --and I mean exactly that-- on a large scale in his work on the philosophy of logic and language as written mainly between 1890 and his death in 1925 (much of which published posthumously) and possibly earlier. I use ‘plagiarize' (or 'plagiarise’) merely as a descriptive term. The essay is not concerned with finger pointing or casting moral judgement. The point is rather to demonstrate carefully by means of detailed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dinnāga's views on reasoning (svārthānumāna).Richard P. Hayes - 1980 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 8 (3):219-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Classes, why and how.Thomas Schindler - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (2):407-435.
    This paper presents a new approach to the class-theoretic paradoxes. In the first part of the paper, I will distinguish classes from sets, describe the function of class talk, and present several reasons for postulating type-free classes. This involves applications to the problem of unrestricted quantification, reduction of properties, natural language semantics, and the epistemology of mathematics. In the second part of the paper, I will present some axioms for type-free classes. My approach is loosely based on the Gödel–Russell idea (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Problem of Foundation in Early Nyāya and in Navya-Nyāya.Eberhard Guhe - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (2):97-113.
    The evaluation of arguments was not the sole concern of logicians in ancient India. Early Nyāya and the later Navya-Nyāya provide an interesting example of the interaction between logic and ontology. In their attempt to develop a kind of property-location logic Naiyāyikas had to consider what kind of restrictions they should impose on the residence relation between a property and its locus. Can we admit circular residence relations or infinitely descending chains of properties, each depending on its successor as its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Errant Fragment of Theophrastus.H. B. Gottschalk - 1992 - Classical Quarterly 42 (02):529-533.
    There are a number of fragments attributed to Theophrastus, as well as titles in Diogenes Laertius' catalogue of his writings , of which it is uncertain whether they should be placed among his logical or rhetorical works. In this note I want to give my reasons for excluding one of them from my forthcoming edition of his logical fragments. It is not my intention here to discuss all the questions it raises; I hope to come back to them in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Social logics and expert systems.Giorgio Sacchi - 1994 - AI and Society 8 (1):84-87.
    My goal is to emphasize the way we generally use the word ‘logic’ and the sort of problems related to the definition of logic and the sort of problems related to the definition of logic. I also wish to underline the differences between human intelligence and artificial intelligence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Byzantine Liar.Stamatios Gerogiorgakis - 2009 - History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (4):313-330.
    An eleventh-century Greek text, in which a fourth-century patristic text is discussed, gives an outline of a solution to the Liar Paradox. The eleventh-century text is probably the first medieval treatment of the Liar. Long passages from both texts are translated in this article. The solution to the Liar Paradox, which they entail, is analysed and compared with the results of modern scholarship on several Latin solutions to this paradox. It is found to be a solution, which bears some analogies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Analysis versus laws boole’s explanatory psychologism versus his explanatory anti-psychologism.Nicla Vassallo - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (3):151-163.
    This paper discusses George Boole’s two distinct approaches to the explanatory relationship between logical and psychological theory. It is argued that, whereas in his first book he attributes a substantive role to psychology in the foundation of logical theory, in his second work he abandons that position in favour of a linguistically conceived foundation. The early Boole espoused a type of psychologism and later came to adopt a type of anti-psychologism. To appreciate this invites a far-reaching reassessment of his philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Le parti E l'intero nella concezione di aristotele: La holologia come progetto di metafisica descrittiva (parte I). [REVIEW]Luigi Dappiano - 1993 - Axiomathes 4 (1):75-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Le parti E l'intero nella concezione di aristotele la holologia come progetto di metafisica descrittiva parte II.Luigi Dappiano - 1993 - Axiomathes 4 (2):227-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Principle of Reductio ad Absurdum Against a Comparative Background.Janusz Chmielewski - 1978 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 8:138-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Charles S. Peirce and the Medieval Doctrine of consequentiae.Francesco Bellucci - 2016 - History and Philosophy of Logic 37 (3):244-268.
    In 1898 C. S. Peirce declares that the medieval doctrine of consequences had been the starting point of his logical investigations in the 1860s. This paper shows that Peirce studied the scholastic theory of consequentiae as early as 1866–67, that he adopted the scholastics’ terminology, and that that theory constituted a source of logical doctrine that sustained Peirce for a lifetime of creative and original work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Logic and the Quest for the Quantification of the Predicate.Bert Mosselmans - 2008 - Foundations of Science 13 (3-4):195-198.
    This paper examines the quest for the quantification of the predicate, as discussed by W.S. Jevons, and relates it to the discussion about universals and particulars between Plato and Aristotle. We conclude that the quest for the quantification of the predicate can only be achieved by stripping the syllogism from its metaphysical heritage.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bocheński’s model of the development of logic.Marcin Tkaczyk - 2021 - Studies in East European Thought 74 (2):211-224.
    According to Bocheński’s description of the history of formal logic, there clearly is some objective development, though far from being cumulative or linear. The history of logic throughout the world consists of three relatively short pinnacles preceded by also short periods of awakening and followed by periods of extensive commentary running into long periods of standstill and decadence, when nearly all achievements are consigned to oblivion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Nevyřešené slabiny extenzionalismu.Marta Vlasáková - 2008 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 15 (1):29-40.
    The nominalist attitude in medieval logic supported a fully extensional conception of the sense of expressions. Many arguments against this approach were raised at that time. I would like to show in this article that there is a extensional conception of notions in current logic, namely in the interpretation of formal theories and the creation models of them and that, and how, traditional arguments against the extensional conception are relevant also for logic today.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic and Mathematics in the Seventeenth Century.Massimo Mugnai - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (4):297-314.
    According to the received view (Bocheński, Kneale), from the end of the fourteenth to the second half of nineteenth century, logic enters a period of decadence. If one looks at this period, the richness of the topics and the complexity of the discussions that characterized medieval logic seem to belong to a completely different world: a simplified theory of the syllogism is the only surviving relic of a glorious past. Even though this negative appraisal is grounded on good reasons, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Twardowski's theory of modification againts the background of traditional logic.Roberto Poli - 1993 - Axiomathes 4 (1):41-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Essay Review.Volker Peckhaus - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (2):115-120.
    Jarmo Pulkkinen, The threat of logical mathematism. A study on the critique of mathematical logic in Germany at the turn of the 20th century. Frankfurt a.M:Peter Lang, 1994. Scandinavian University Studies in the Humanities and Social Sciences; 7). 186 pp. 24 DM. ISBN 3-631-47409-1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cracow Circle and Its Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics.Roman Murawski - 2015 - Axiomathes 25 (3):359-376.
    The paper is devoted to the presentation and analysis of the philosophical views concerning logic and mathematics of the leading members of Cracow Circle, i.e., of Jan Salamucha, Jan Franciszek Drewnowski and Józef Maria Bocheński. Their views on the problem of possible applicability of logical tools in metaphysical and theological researches is also discussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations