Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Carnap, Feyerabend, and the Pragmatic Theory of Observation.Daniel Kuby - 2018 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 8 (2):432-470.
    Paul Feyerabend once made a remark to the effect that his pragmatic theory of observation can be traced back to proposals put forward by leading Logical Empiricists during the height of the protocol sentence debate. In this paper I want to vindicate the systematic side of Feyerabend’s remark and show that a pragmatic theory of observation can in fact be found in Rudolf Carnap’s writings of 1932. I first proceed to dispel a misunderstanding concerning the term “pragmatic” raised by Thomas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Systematic realism.C. A. Hooker - 1974 - Synthese 26 (3-4):409 - 497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • La crítica de Paul Karl Feyerabend al modelo neo-positivista del significado.María Teresa Gargiulo de Vázquez - 2014 - Arbor 190 (769):a168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paul Feyerabend.John Preston - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Paul Feyerabend and the problem of theorethical entities.Fernando Tula Molina - 2005 - Scientiae Studia 3 (2):257-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Empiricism, perception and conceptual change.Cliff A. Hooker - 1973 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (September):59-74.
    In recent times it has become fashionable to emphasize the role of conceptual change in the history of science. To judge from recent writers, every significant theoretical change in science is first and foremost a revolution in scientific concepts—a conceptual revolution. According to this view, every level of experience is affected by each fundamental theoretical change: physical theory, experimental practice and even perceptual experience. The Aristotelian patrician who watched the sun sink beneath the horizon not only had different beliefs about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Incommensurability, types of phenomena and relevant incompatibility.Esteban Céspedes - 2018 - Cinta de Moebio 63:323-330.
    Resumen: This is the first part of a three-part paper on incommensurability. Although incommensurability between theories has been object of study during many years, there does not seem to be a clear consensus regarding the notion of meaning according to which it should be characterised. Based on the notion of incommensurability proposed here, the common ground between incommensurable theories is neither determined by the sense nor by the reference of the relevant terms, but by a given phenomenon type, which fixes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Remarks on concept formation: Theory building and theory testing.Joseph M. Firestone - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (4):570-604.
    Concepts originating in the philosophy of science generally are used only ritualistically and in careful isolation from research practice in political science. But philosophical considerations are fundamental to political research, and critically influence its decisions. The question is whether ideas offered by philosophers of science have practical (that is to say, theoretical) significance for political researchers. This essay argues that philosophy of science has extremely relevant ideas to offer. The argument proceeds through an initial presentation of some elementary notions drawn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark