Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Virtue, mixed emotions and moral ambivalence.David Carr - 2009 - Philosophy 84 (1):31-46.
    Aristotelian virtue ethics invests emotions and feelings with much moral significance. However, the moral and other conflicts that inevitably beset human life often give rise to states of emotional division and ambivalence with problematic implications for any understanding of virtue as complete psychic unity of character and conduct. For one thing, any admission that the virtuous are prey to conflicting passions and desires may seem to threaten the crucial virtue ethical distinction between the virtuous and the continent. One recent attempt (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Music, meaning, and emotion.David Carr - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (3):225–234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Educating the whole child: social-emotional learning and ethics education.Nikolaus J. Barkauskas & Michael D. Burroughs - 2017 - Ethics and Education 12 (2):218-232.
    Research supporting social and emotional learning in schools demonstrates numerous benefits for students, including increased academic achievement and social and emotional competencies. However, research supporting the adoption of SEL lacks a clear conception of ethical competence. This lack of clarity is problematic for two reasons. First, it contributes to the conflation of social, emotional, and ethical competencies. Second, as a result, insufficient attention is paid to the related, yet distinct, ends of social-emotional and ethical education. While supporting SEL we critique (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A danger of definition: Polar predicates in moral theory.Mark Alfano - 2009 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 3 (3):1-14.
    In this paper, I use an example from the history of philosophy to show how independently defining each side of a pair of contrary predicates is apt to lead to contradiction. In the Euthyphro, piety is defined as that which is loved by some of the gods while impiety is defined as that which is hated by some of the gods. Socrates points out that since the gods harbor contrary sentiments, some things are both pious and impious. But “pious” and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Emotional intelligence and moral agency: Some worries and a suggestion.Sophie Rietti - 2009 - Philosophical Psychology 22 (2):143 – 165.
    Emotional intelligence (EI) has been put forward as a distinctive kind of intelligence and, by popularizers such as Daniel Goleman, as an indicator of moral and life skills. Critics, however, have been concerned EI-testing measures conformity or the ability to manipulate own or others' emotions, and relies on a problematic assumption that there are definitive, universal “right” answers when it comes to feelings. Such worries have also been raised about the original concept developed by Peter Salovey and John D. Mayer; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tin Men: Ethics, Cybernetics and the Importance of Soul.Valerie Morkevicius - 2014 - Journal of Military Ethics 13 (1):3-19.
    (2014). Tin Men: Ethics, Cybernetics and the Importance of Soul. Journal of Military Ethics: Vol. 13, No. 1, pp. 3-19. doi: 10.1080/15027570.2014.908011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The trouble with ambivalent emotions.Kristján Kristjánsson - 2010 - Philosophy 85 (4):485-510.
    Mixed or ambivalent emotions have long intrigued philosophers. I dissect various putative cases of emotional ambivalence and conclude that the alleged 'psychological problem' surrounding them admits of a solution. That problem has, however, often been conflated with 'moral problem' - of how one should react morally to such ambivalence — which remains active even after the psychological one has been solved. I discuss how the moral problem hits hardest at virtue ethics, old and new. I distinguish between particularist and generalist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Phronesis as an ideal in professional medical ethics: some preliminary positionings and problematics.Kristján Kristjánsson - 2015 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 36 (5):299-320.
    Phronesis has become a buzzword in contemporary medical ethics. Yet, the use of this single term conceals a number of significant conceptual controversies based on divergent philosophical assumptions. This paper explores three of them: on phronesis as universalist or relativist, generalist or particularist, and natural/painless or painful/ambivalent. It also reveals tensions between Alasdair MacIntyre’s take on phronesis, typically drawn upon in professional ethics discourses, and Aristotle’s original concept. The paper offers these four binaries as a possible analytical framework for classifying (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • “Emotional intelligence” in the classroom? An aristotelian critique.Kristjan Kristjansson - 2006 - Educational Theory 56 (1):39-56.
    A recent trend in moral education, social and emotional learning, incorporates the mantra of emotional intelligence as a key element in an extensive program of character building. In making his famous claim that the good life would have to include appropriate emotions, Aristotle obviously considered the schooling of emotions to be an indispensable part of moral education. However, in this essay Kristján Kristjánsson casts doubt on the assumption that Aristotelians should approve of the clarion call for EI, as understood by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations