Switch to: References

Citations of:

Theory of experimental inference

New York,: Macmillan (1948)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Epistemology as General Systems Theory: An Approach to the Design of Complex Decision-Making Experiments.Ian I. Mitroff & Francisco Sagasti - 1973 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 3 (2):117-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Epistemic Trust in Science.Torsten Wilholt - 2013 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64 (2):233-253.
    Epistemic trust is crucial for science. This article aims to identify the kinds of assumptions that are involved in epistemic trust as it is required for the successful operation of science as a collective epistemic enterprise. The relevant kind of reliance should involve working from the assumption that the epistemic endeavors of others are appropriately geared towards the truth, but the exact content of this assumption is more difficult to analyze than it might appear. The root of the problem is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Historical objectivity and value neutrality.James Leach - 1968 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 11 (1-4):349 – 367.
    To resolve the impasse between skeptic, idealist and positivist as to whether or not historical inquiry can be objective, an affirmative answer is argued by exposing, clarifying and challenging the common presupposition: the thesis of scientific value neutrality. The argument applies a more explicit version of the Braithwaite— Churchman-Rudner position to history and thus challenges the prevalent claim that history, unlike the law, has but one goal, the establishment of truth about the past. The important yet neglected residual issue concerns (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Speculative Philosophy of Science vs. Logical Positivism: Preliminary Round.Joel Katzav - forthcoming - In Sander Verhaegh (ed.), American Philosophy and the Intellectual Migration: Pragmatism, Logical Empiricism, Phenomenology, Critical Theory. Berlin: De Gruyter.
    I outline the theoretical framework of, and three research programs within American speculative philosophy of science during the period 1900-1931. One program applies verificationism to research in psychology, one investigates the methodology of research programs, and one analyses scientific explanation and other scientific concepts. The primary sources for my outline are works by Morris Raphael Cohen, Grace Andrus de Laguna, Theodore de Laguna, Edgar Arthur Singer Jr., Harold Robert Smart, and Marie Collins Swabey. I also use my outline to provide (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The limits of conventional justification: inductive risk and industry bias beyond conventionalism.Miguel Ohnesorge - 2020 - Frontiers in Research Metric and Analytics 14.
    This article develops a constructive criticism of methodological conventionalism. Methodological conventionalism asserts that standards of inductive risk ought to be justified in virtue of their ability to facilitate coordination in a research community. On that view, industry bias occurs when conventional methodological standards are violated to foster industry preferences. The underlying account of scientific conventionality, however, is problematically incomplete. Conventions may be justified in virtue of their coordinative functions, but often qualify for posterior empirical criticism as research advances. Accordingly, industry (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Error Is in the Gap: Synthesizing Accounts for Societal Values in Science.Christopher ChoGlueck - 2018 - Philosophy of Science 85 (4):704-725.
    Kevin Elliott and others separate two common arguments for the legitimacy of societal values in scientific reasoning as the gap and the error arguments. This article poses two questions: How are these two arguments related, and what can we learn from their interrelation? I contend that we can better understand the error argument as nested within the gap because the error is a limited case of the gap with narrower features. Furthermore, this nestedness provides philosophers with conceptual tools for analyzing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Inductive risk: does it really refute value-freedom?Markus Dressel - 2022 - Theoria 37 (2):181-207.
    The argument from inductive risk is considered to be one of the strongest challenges for value-free science. A great part of its appeal lies in the idea that even an ideal epistemic agent—the “perfect scientist” or “scientist qua scientist”—cannot escape inductive risk. In this paper, I scrutinize this ambition by stipulating an idealized Bayesian decision setting. I argue that inductive risk does not show that the “perfect scientist” must, descriptively speaking, make non-epistemic value-judgements, at least not in a way that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Climate Simulations: Uncertain Projections for an Uncertain World.Rafaela Hillerbrand - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (1):17-32.
    Between the fourth and the recent fifth IPCC report, science as well as policy making have made great advances in dealing with uncertainties in global climate models. However, the uncertainties public decision making has to deal with go well beyond what is currently addressed by policy makers and climatologists alike. It is shown in this paper that within an anthropocentric framework, a whole hierarchy of models from various scientific disciplines is needed for political decisions as regards climate change. Via what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A mathematical model of Churchmanian inquiring systems with special reference to Popper's measures for?The Severity of Tests?Ian I. Mitroff, Frederick Betz & Richard O. Mason - 1970 - Theory and Decision 1 (2):155-178.
    Through the use of Bayesian probability theory and Communication theory, a formal mathematical model of a Churchmanian Dialectical Inquirer is developed. The Dialectical Inquirer is based on Professor C. West Churchman's novel interpretation and application of Hegelian dialectics to decision theory. The result is not only the empirical application of dialectical inquiry but also its empirical (i.e., scientific) investigation. The Dialectical Inquirer is seen as especially suited to problems in strategic policy formation and in decision theory. Finally, specific application of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What it means to respect individuality.Xiaofei Liu & Ye Liang - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (8):2579-2598.
    Using pure statistical evidence about a group to judge a particular member of that group is often found objectionable. One natural explanation of why this is objectionable appeals to the moral notion of respecting individuality: to properly respect individuality, we need individualized evidence, not pure statistical evidence. However, this explanation has been criticized on the ground that there is no fundamental difference between the so-called “individualized evidence” and “pure statistical evidence”. This paper defends the respecting-individuality explanation by developing an account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Book Reviews : Creating a Dialectical Social Science. BY IAN I. MITROFF and RICHARD O. MASON. Theory and Decision Library, Volume 25. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1981. Pp. ix + 189. $33.00. [REVIEW]Paul Diesing - 1985 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 15 (2):232-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Design Rules: Industrial Research and Epistemic Merit.Torsten Wilholt - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (1):66-89.
    A common complaint against the increasing privatization of research is that research that is conducted with the immediate purpose of producing applicable knowledge will not yield knowledge as valuable as that generated in more curiosity‐driven, academic settings. In this paper, I make this concern precise and reconstruct the rationale behind it. Subsequently, I examine the case of industry research on the giant magnetoresistance effect in the 1990s as a characteristic example of research undertaken under considerable pressure to produce applicable results. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Knowledge for whom?William Evan - 1987 - Social Epistemology 1 (2):155 – 162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reviews. [REVIEW]Ilkka Niiniluoto & Ronald Giere - 1975 - Synthese 31 (1):161-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the seriousness of mistakes.Isaac Levi - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (1):47-65.
    Several authors have recently contended that modern statistical theory provides a powerful argument in favor of the view that if scientists accept or reject hypotheses at all they do so only in a behavioral sense--i.e., in a sense which reduces "accepting P" to "acting on the basis of P relative to an objective O". In this paper, the argument from statistics in favor of a behavioral view is outlined; an interpretation of two statistical procedures (Bayes method and signifigance testing) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • A unifying typology of information.B. Antal Banathy - 1997 - World Futures 49 (3):369-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dialectical pragmatism.Ian I. Mitroff & Richard O. Mason - 1981 - Synthese 47 (1):29 - 42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Brunswik Lens Model of Dialectical Inquiring Systems.Ian I. Mitroff - 1974 - Theory and Decision 5 (1):45-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Context of Communication: What Philosophers can Contribute.Wayne C. Myrvold - unknown
    Once an experiment is done, the observations have been made and the data have been analyzed, what should scientists communicate to the world at large, and how should they do it? This, I will argue, is an intricate question, and one that philosophers can make a contribution to. I will illustrate these points by reference to the debate between Fisher and Neyman & Pearson in the 1950s, which I take to be, at heart, a debate about norms of scientific communication. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark