Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Vitalism and panpsychism in the philosophy of Anne Conway.Olivia Branscum - forthcoming - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-22.
    Anne Conway (1631–1679) is often described as a vitalist. Scholars typically take this to mean that Conway considers life to be ubiquitous throughout the world. While Conway is indeed a vitalist in this sense, I argue that she is also committed to a stronger view: namely, the panpsychist view that mental capacities are ubiquitous and fundamental in creation. Reading Conway as a panpsychist highlights several aspects of her philosophy that deserve further attention, especially her accounts of emanative causation and universal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Like a Cypress among Pliant Shrubs. Kabbalah and Reformed Orthodoxy in the Philologia Sacra of Jacob Rhenferd (1654–1712). [REVIEW]Marcello Cattaneo - 2023 - Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 86 (1):261-292.
    Jacob Rhenferd (1654–1712), professor of Hebrew and Oriental languages at the University of Franeker in the United Provinces, is a mostly forgotten figure. This article analyses his theological and historical scholarship, with special attention to his use of Jewish mystical texts. It argues that Rhenferd’s conception of philologia sacra was profoundly shaped by kabbalistic insights and that a recourse to Kabbalah provided him with an idiom to articulate anew some foundational Reformed doctrines. Conversely, a comparison with the kabbalistic studies of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Henry More against the Lurianic Kabbalah. The Arguments in the Fundamenta.Giuliana Di Biase - 2022 - Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia 1:19-35.
    The Cambridge Platonist Henry More was fiercely averse to the Lurianic Kabbalah, with which he became acquainted through the two tomes of the Kabbala denudata. More contributed to the first tome substantially and was highly influential in shaping the reception of this work, edited by Christian Knorr von Rosenroth. He denounced the incompatibility of the Christian religion with Luria's system and in his last contribution, the Fundamenta, he put forward an apagogical argument meant to show the inconsistency of Luria's teaching. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • God, space and the Spirit of Nature: Morean trialism revisited.Jacques Joseph - 2024 - Intellectual History Review 34 (1):165-184.
    In my paper, I dispute Christian Hengstermann’s analysis of More’s philosophical system as a form of panentheistic panpsychism in which matter is alive by virtue of being the last emanation from God. I show that, in his mature period, More explicitly rejected such an emanationist doctrine and attributed the non-mechanical powers of matter to an outside immaterial principle, the Spirit of Nature. Ultimately, this leads to a system in which divine space, the Spirit of Nature and the spirit of God (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three texts on the Kabbalah: More, Wachter, Leibniz, and the philosophy of the Hebrews.Mogens Lærke - 2017 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (5):1011-1030.
    The article reconstructs a brief controversy between H. More, G. W. Leibniz and J. G. Wachter about the Kabbalah, or what they called ‘the philosophy of the Hebrews’. I study in particular the status of the proposition ‘nothing comes out of nothing’ in their exchanges - a proposition they all agreed was a fundamental kabbalist axiom while having differing views as to the prospects of reconciling that position with Christianity. I show how Wachter’s curious Kabbalistico-Spinozism provided the stage for an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Peirce's ‘Schelling-Fashioned Idealism’ and ‘the Monstrous Mysticism of the East’.Paul Franks - 2015 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (4):732-755.
    Peirce remarks on several occasions in the 1790s on affinities between his evolutionary metaphysics and Schelling's Idealism, behind which, he avers, lies ‘the monstrous mysticism of the East’. What are these affinities? Why are they affinities with Schelling rather than with Hegel? And what is the mysticism in question? I argue that Schelling, like Peirce but unlike Hegel, is committed to evolution, not only across species boundaries, but also across the boundary between the inorganic and the organic. Moreover, Schelling, like (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The philosophical systems of Francesco Patrizi and Henry More.Jacques Joseph - 2019 - Intellectual History Review 29 (4):595-617.
    Some connection between the philosophy of Henry More and Francesco Patrizi is often assumed but rarely receives detailed attention.1 When it does, researchers’ attention tends to focus on their doc...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Henry More on Material and Spiritual Extension.Jasper Reid - 2003 - Dialogue 42 (3):531-.
    RÉSUMÉ: Cet article examine les façons dont le platonicien de Cambridge Henry More, au XVIIe siècle, a tenté de défendre une rigoureuse séparation ontologique entre les substances matérielles et les substances spirituelles tout en maintenant que les unes et les autres étaient étendues. Nous élucidons certaines des théories et certains des concepts propres à More, tels que l’indiscerpabilité, la pénétrabilité, la spissitude essentielle et l’hylopathie, qui fournissaient, croyait-il, une base solide à cette séparation. Mais nous montrons aussi certaines faiblesses inhérentes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Anne Viscountess Conway: A Seventeenth Century Rationalist.Jane Duran - 1989 - Hypatia 4 (1):64 - 79.
    The work of Spinoza, Descartes and Leibniz is cited in an attempt to develop, both expositorily and critically, the philosophy of Anne Viscountess Conway. Broadly, it is contended that Conway's metaphysics, epistemology and account of the passions not only bear intriguing comparison with the work of the other well-known rationalists, but supersede them in some ways, particularly insofar as the notions of substance and ontological hierarchy are concerned. Citing the commentary of Loptson and Carolyn Merchant, and alluding to other commentary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations