Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Is there a Newton of the blade of grass?Peter Schuster - 2011 - Complexity 16 (6):5-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Epigenesis: The newer synthesis?Glendon Schubert - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):24-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Decisions, Decisions: Why Thomas Hunt Morgan Was Not the “Father” of Evo‐Devo.Jeffrey H. Schwartz - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (5):918-929.
    Although the construction of neo-Darwinism grew out of Thomas Hunt Morgan's melding of Darwinism and Mendelism, his evidence did not soley support a model of gradual change. To the contrary, he was confronted with observations that could have led him to a more "evo-devo" understanding of the emergence of novel features. Indeed, since Morgan was an embryologist before he became a fruit-fly geneticist, one would have predicted that the combination of these two lines of research would have resulted in early (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Dualism and conflicts in understanding speciation.Menno Schilthuizen - 2000 - Bioessays 22 (12):1134-1141.
    Speciation is a central but elusive issue in evolutionary biology. Over the past sixty years, the subject has been studied within a framework conceived by Ernst Mayr and Theodosius Dobzhansky and subsequently developed further by numerous other workers. In this “isolation” theory, the evolution of reproductive isolation is a key element of speciation; natural selection is given only secondary importance while gene flow is considered prohibitive to the process. In this paper, I argue that certain elements in this approach have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Adaptive modification of behavior: Processing information from the environment.Wolfgang M. Schleidt - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):158-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are computer scientists the sutlers of modern biology?: Bioinformatics is indispensible for progress in molecular life sciences but does not get credit for its contributions.Peter Schuster - 2014 - Complexity 19 (4):10-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nature of developmental constraints and the difference-Maker argument for externalism.Roger Sansom - 2009 - Biology and Philosophy 24 (4):441-459.
    One current version of the internalism/externalism debate in evolutionary theory focuses on the relative importance of developmental constraints in evolutionary explanation. The received view of developmental constraints sees them as an internalist concept that tend to be shared across related species as opposed to selective pressures that are not. Thus, to the extent that constraints can explain anything, they can better explain similarity across species, while natural selection is better able to explain their differences. I challenge both of these aspects (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The connectionist framework for Gene regulation.Roger Sansom - 2008 - Biology and Philosophy 23 (4):475-491.
    I show that gene regulation networks are qualitatively consistent and therefore sufficiently similar to linearly seperable connectionist networks to warrant that the connectionist framework be applied to gene regulation. On this view, natural selection designs gene regulation networks to overcome the difficulty of development. I offer some general lessons about their evolvability that can be learned by examining the generic features of connectionist networks.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Anthropocentricisms in cladograms.Hanno Sandvik - 2009 - Biology and Philosophy 24 (4):425-440.
    Both written and graphic accounts of history can be biased by the perspective of the historian. O’Hara (Biol Philos 7:135–160, 1992) has demonstrated that this also applies to evolutionary history and its historians, and identified four narrative devices that introduce anthropocentricisms into accounts of phylogeny. In the current paper, I identify a fifth such narrative device, viz. the left–right ordering of the taxa at the tips of cladograms. I define two measures that make it possible to quantify the degree of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The world represented as a hierarchy of nature may not require “species”.Stanley N. Salthe - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):300-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nietzsche, Darwin e a questão do progresso evolutivo.Emmanuel Salanskis - 2018 - Discurso 48 (2):95-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Current Perspectives in Philosophy of Biology.Joaquin Suarez Ruiz & Rodrigo A. Lopez Orellana - 2019 - Humanities Journal of Valparaiso 14:7-426.
    Current Perspectives in Philosophy of Biology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why I am an accommodationist and proud of it.Michael Ruse - 2015 - Zygon 50 (2):361-375.
    There is a strong need of a reasoned defense of what was known as the “independence” position of the science–religion relationship but that more recently has been denigrated as the “accommodationist” position, namely that while there are parts of religion—fundamentalist Christianity in particular—that clash with modern science, the essential parts of religion do not and could not clash with science. A case for this position is made on the grounds of the essentially metaphorical nature of science. Modern science functions because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Why did the stegosaurus have plates, or is biology second-rate because it thinks in therms of ends?Michael Ruse - 2019 - Humanities Journal of Valparaiso 14:9-25.
    There is something distinctively different about explanation in the biological sciences, as opposed to explanation in the physical sciences. In the former one has functional arguments, arguments making reference to what Aristotle called “final causes.” As in: “The function of the plates on the back of the Stegosaurus was to keep the body at a constant temperature.” Since the Scientific Revolution, such explanations have been forbidden in the physical sciences. Does this then mean that biology is second rate, as is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science and values: My debt to Ernan McMullin.Michael Ruse - 2012 - Zygon 47 (4):666-685.
    Ernan McMullin's 1982 presidential address to the Philosophy of Science Association dealt with the issue of science and values, arguing that although scientists are rightfully wary of the infiltration of cultural and social values, their work is guided by “epistemic values,” such as the drive for consistency and predictive fertility. McMullin argued that it is the pursuit of these epistemic values that drives nonepistemic values from science. Using the case study of the fate of the nonepistemic value of progress in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Species as individuals: Logical, biological, and philosophical problems.Michael Ruse - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):299-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Confessions of an Agnostic: Apologia Pro Vita Sua.Michael Ruse - 2021 - Sophia 60 (3):575-591.
    Francis Collins, the director of the NEH and well-known Christian, has said that agnosticism is a bit of a cop-out. Either be a Christian or be an atheism, but have the guts to make up your mind. I shall argue in a positive way for agnosticism, showing that it can be as vibrant a position as belief or non-belief. It gives you a renewed appreciation of life and the world in which we live.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explaining diversity and searching for general processes: Isn't there a middle ground?Paul Rozin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):157-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Protozoa, protista, protoctista: What's in a name?Lynn J. Rothschild - 1989 - Journal of the History of Biology 22 (2):277-305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Typologies: Obstacles and opportunities in scientific change.Alexander Rosenberg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):298-299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The notion of progress in evolutionary biology – the unresolved problem and an empirical suggestion.Bernd Rosslenbroich - 2006 - Biology and Philosophy 21 (1):41-70.
    Modern biology is ambivalent about the notion of evolutionary progress. Although most evolutionists imply in their writings that they still understand large-scale macroevolution as a somewhat progressive process, the use of the term “progress” is increasingly criticized and avoided. The paper shows that this ambivalence has a long history and results mainly from three problems: (1) The term “progress” carries historical, theoretical and social implications which are not congruent with modern knowledge of the course of evolution; (2) An incongruence exists (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The importance of homology for biology and philosophy.Ingo Brigandt & Paul Edmund Griffiths - 2007 - Biology and Philosophy 22 (5):633-641.
    Editors' introduction to the special issue on homology (Biology and Philosophy Vol. 22, Issue 5, 2007).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Are there culturgens?Alexander Rosenberg - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):22-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metacomparative psychology.Herbert L. Roitblat - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):677.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Alfred Russel Wallace, antropólogo: contribuciones a la antropología física.Juan Manuel Rodríguez Caso - 2020 - Arbor 196 (797):565.
    La figura de Alfred Russel Wallace dentro de la antropología ha sido escasamente reconocida dentro de la historia de la disciplina. Un punto importante es ubicar al autor dentro de las discusiones antropológicas de la época victoriana, desde su interés temprano como naturalista por historizar a los seres humanos, hasta su labor institucional como el primer presidente de un departamento de antropología en Inglaterra. En ese contexto, el objetivo del trabajo es presentar la visión de Wallace respecto a la antropología (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Continuity, Naturalism, and Contingency: A Theology of Evolution Drawing on the Semiotics of C. S. Peirce and Trinitarian Thought.Andrew J. Robinson - 2004 - Zygon 39 (1):111-136.
    The starting point for this article is the question of the relationship between Darwinism and Christian theology. I suggest that evolutionary theory presents three broad issues of relevance to theology: the phenomena ofcontinuity, naturalism, andcontingency. In order to formulate a theological response to these issues I draw on the semiotics (theory of signs) and cosmology of the American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce. Peirce developed a triadic theory of signs, underpinned by a threefold system of metaphysical categories. I propose a semiotic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Vertebrate evolution: The developmental origins of adult variation.Michael K. Richardson - 1999 - Bioessays 21 (7):604-613.
    Many biologists assume, as Darwin did, that natural selection acts mainly on late embryonic or postnatal development. This view is consistent with von Baer's observations of morphological divergence at late stages. It is also suggested by the conserved morphology and common molecular genetic mechanisms of pattern formation seen in embryos. I argue here, however, that differences in adult morphology may be generated at a variety of stages. Natural selection may have a major action on developmental mechanisms during the organogenetic period, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • In the Light of the Environment: Evolution Through Biogrammars Not Programmers.Ken Richardson - 2020 - Biological Theory 15 (4):212-222.
    Biological understanding of human cognitive functions is incomplete because of failure to understand the evolution of complex functions and organisms in general. Here, that failure is attributed to an aspect of the standard neo-Darwinian synthesis, namely commitment to evolution by natural selection of genetic programs in stable environments, a position that cannot easily explain the evolution of complexity. When we turn to consider more realistic, highly changeable environments, however, another possibility becomes clearer. An alternative to genetic programs—dubbed “biogrammars”—is proposed here (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Searching for Darwinism in Generalized Darwinism.Thomas A. C. Reydon & Markus Scholz - 2015 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (3):561-589.
    While evolutionary thinking is increasingly becoming popular in fields of investigation outside the biological sciences, it remains unclear how helpful it is there and whether it actually yields good explanations of the phenomena under study. Here we examine the ontology of a recent approach to applying evolutionary thinking outside biology, the generalized Darwinism approach proposed by Geoffrey Hodgson and Thorbjørn Knudsen. We examine the ontology of populations in biology and in GD, and argue that biological evolutionary theory sets ontological criteria (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • David N. Stamos (2003). The species problem: Biological species, ontology, and the metaphysics of biology.Thomas Reydon - 2004 - Acta Biotheoretica 52 (3):229-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Known general principles of learning cannot be ignored.Sam Revusky - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):156-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human sociobiology.Michael J. Reiss - 1984 - Zygon 19 (2):117-140.
    Sociobiology is the scientific study of why organisms sometimes associate with other organisms. This paper surveys recent research on the reasons for altruism and aggression. It also considers the contributions an individual's genes and its environment make to its behavior, and it reviews functional theories for the evolution of cannibalism, polygamy, homosexuality, and infanticide in humans and other animals. Finally mention is made of the limited and generally negative attitude of sociobiology to religion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The demise of mental representations.Edward S. Reed - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):297-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Reviews : Ilse N. Bulhof, The Language of Science. A Study of the Relationship between Literature and Science in the Perspective of a Hermeneutical Ontology with a Case Study of Darwin's The Origin of Species. E. J. Brill, Leiden, 1992. Pp. 207. $57.14. [REVIEW]Ronald Curtis - 1994 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 24 (4):510-516.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Race and language in the Darwinian tradition (and what Darwin's language–species parallels have to do with it).Gregory Radick - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 39 (3):359-370.
    What should human languages be like if humans are the products of Darwinian evolution? Between Darwin’s day & like the peoples speaking them are higher or lower in an evolutionarily generated scale This paper charts some of the changes in the Darwinian tradition that transformed the notion of human linguistic equality from creationist heresy., our own, expectations about evolution’s imprint on language have changed dramaticallyIt is now a commonplace that, for good Darwinian reasons, no language is more highly evolved than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Learning theory in its niche.Howard Rachlin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):155-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Charles Girard: Relationships and Representation in Nineteenth Century Systematics.Aleta Quinn - 2017 - Journal of the History of Biology 50 (3):609-643.
    Early nineteenth century systematists sought to describe what they called the Natural System or the Natural Classification. In the nineteenth century, there was no agreement about the basis of observed patterns of similarity between organisms. What did these systematists think they were doing, when they named taxa, proposed relationships between taxa, and arranged taxa into representational schemes? In this paper I explicate Charles Frederic Girard’s (1822–1895) theory and method of systematics. A student of Louis Agassiz, and subsequently (1850–1858) a collaborator (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Resolving Multiple Visions of Nature, Science, and Religion.James D. Proctor - 2004 - Zygon 39 (3):637-657.
    I argue for the centrality of the concepts of biophysical and human nature in science-and-religion studies, consider five different metaphors, or “visions,” of nature, and explore possibilities and challenges in reconciling them. These visions include (a) evolutionary nature, built on the powerful explanatory framework of evolutionary theory; (b) emergent nature, arising from recent research in complex systems and self-organization; (c) malleable nature, indicating both the recombinant potential of biotechnology and the postmodern challenge to a fixed ontology; (d) nature as sacred, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the road to the Origin with Darwin, Hooker, and Gray.Duncan M. Porter - 1993 - Journal of the History of Biology 26 (1):1-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • How Fast Does Darwin’s Elephant Population Grow?János Podani, Ádám Kun & András Szilágyi - 2018 - Journal of the History of Biology 51 (2):259-281.
    In “The Origin of Species,” Darwin describes a hypothetical example illustrating that large, slowly reproducing mammals such as the elephant can reach very large numbers if population growth is not affected by regulating factors. The elephant example has since been cited in various forms in a wide variety of books, ranging from educational material to encyclopedias. However, Darwin’s text was changed over the six editions of the book, although some errors in the mathematics persisted throughout. In addition, full details of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genes, mind, and emotion.Robert Plutchik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):21-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What genetic research on intelligence tells us about the environment.Robert Plomin, Stephen A. Petrill & Alexandra L. Cutting - 1996 - Journal of Biosocial Science 28 (4):587-606.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is an ecological approach radical enough?H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling-Smee - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):154-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Darwinian Dynamics Implies Developmental Ascendency.Ping Ao - 2007 - Biological Theory 2 (1):113-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sewall Wright’s adaptive landscapes: 1932 vs. 1988.Massimo Pigliucci - 2008 - Biology and Philosophy 23 (5):591-603.
    Sewall Wright introduced the metaphor of evolution on “adaptive landscapes” in a pair of papers published in 1931 and 1932. The metaphor has been one of the most influential in modern evolutionary biology, although recent theoretical advancements show that it is deeply flawed and may have actually created research questions that are not, in fact, fecund. In this paper I examine in detail what Wright actually said in the 1932 paper, as well as what he thought of the matter at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Okasha’s evolution and the levels of selection: toward a broader conception of theoretical biology: Oxford University Press, Oxford. [REVIEW]Massimo Pigliucci - 2010 - Biology and Philosophy 25 (3):405-415.
    The debate about the levels of selection has been one of the most controversial both in evolutionary biology and in philosophy of science. Okasha’s book makes the sort of contribution that simply will not be able to be ignored by anyone interested in this field for many years to come. However, my interest here is in highlighting some examples of how Okasha goes about discussing his material to suggest that his book is part of an increasingly interesting trend that sees (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A functional view of learning.Lewis Petrinovich - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):153-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Five Marks of the Mental.Tuomas K. Pernu - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    The mental realm seems different to the physical realm; the mental is thought to be dependent on, yet distinct from the physical. But how, exactly, are the two realms supposed to be different, and what, exactly, creates the seemingly insurmountable juxtaposition between the mental and the physical? This review identifies and discusses five marks of the mental, features that set characteristically mental phenomena apart from the characteristically physical phenomena. These five marks (intentionality, consciousness, free will, teleology, and normativity) are not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Universal grammar and mental continuity: Two modern myths.Derek C. Penn, Keith J. Holyoak & Daniel J. Povinelli - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (5):462-464.
    In our opinion, the discontinuity between extant human and nonhuman minds is much broader and deeper than most researchers admit. We are happy to report that Evans & Levinson's (E&L's) target article strongly corroborates our unpopular hypothesis, and that the comparative evidence, in turn, bolsters E&L's provocative argument. Both a Universal Grammar and the “mental continuity” between human and nonhuman minds turn out to be modern myths.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ecosystem Engineering, Experiment, and Evolution.Trevor Pearce - 2011 - Biology and Philosophy 26 (6):793-812.
    This paper argues that philosophers should pay more attention to the idea of ecosystem engineering and to the scientific literature surrounding it. Ecosystem engineering is a broad but clearly delimited concept that is less subject to many of the “it encompasses too much” criticisms that philosophers have directed at niche construction . The limitations placed on the idea of ecosystem engineering point the way to a narrower idea of niche construction. Moreover, experimental studies in the ecosystem engineering literature provide detailed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations