Switch to: References

Citations of:

Brainstorms

MIT Press (1978)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A matter of opinion.Keith Frankish - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (4):423-442.
    This paper sets out the case for a two-level theory of human psychology. It takes its start from Daniel Dennett.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The contextual stance.Gordon R. Foxall - 1999 - Philosophical Psychology 12 (1):25-46.
    The contention that cognitive psychology and radical behaviorism yield equivalent accounts of decision making and problem solving is examined by contrasting a framework of cognitive interpretation, Dennett's intentional stance, with a corresponding interpretive stance derived from contextualism. The insistence of radical behaviorists that private events such as thoughts and feelings belong in a science of human behavior is indicted in view of their failure to provide a credible interpretation of complex human behavior. Dennett's interpretation of intentional systems is an exemplar (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dream processing.David Foulkes - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):678-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Radical behaviorism is a dead end.Jeff Foss - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):59-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Rachlin's “Pain and behavior”: A lightening of the burden.Wilbert E. Fordyce - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):58-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defence of the armchair.Michael Fortescue - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):135-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why paramecia don't have mental representations.Jerry A. Fodor - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):3-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Searle on what only brains can do.J. A. Fodor - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):431-432.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • A Situated Grandmother? Some Remarks on Proposals by Barwise and Perry.J. A. Fodor - 1987 - Mind and Language 2 (1):64-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Can any statements about human behavior be empirically validated?Baruch Fischoff - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):336-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality is a red herring.Chris Fields & Eric Dietrich - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):756.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Goldman has not defeated folk functionalism.James H. Fetzer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):42-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • So many models – So little time.Jerome A. Feldman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning from instruction.Jerome A. Feldman - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):593-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Treading the primrose path of dalliance in psychology.B. A. Farrell - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is consciousness of perception really separable from perception?Martha J. Farah - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):254-255.
    Although not the main point of his target article, Block defends the view that perception and awareness of perception could be functions of different brain systems. I will argue that the available data do not support this view, and that Block's defense of the view rests on problematic eonstruals of the “executive system” and of the components of information-processing models.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Genetic factors in behaviour: The return of the repressed.Hans J. Eysenck - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):703-704.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Advantage of modeling in neuroscience.J. -P. Ewert - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):438-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Culture, Cognitive Pluralism and Rationality.Colin W. Evers - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (4):364-382.
    This paper considers the prospects for objectivity in reasoning strategies in response to empirical studies that apparently show systematic culture‐based differences in patterns of reasoning. I argue that there is at least one modest class of exceptions to the claim that there are alternative, equally warranted standards of good reasoning: the class that entails the solution of certain well‐structured problems which, suitably chosen, are common, or touchstone, to the sorts of culturally different viewpoints discussed. There is evidence that some cognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On defining rationality unreasonably.J. St B. T. Evans & P. Pollard - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):335-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Information is in the eye of the beholder.Rhea T. Eskew - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):144-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recall or regeneration of past mental states: Toward an account in terms of cognitive processes.K. Anders Ericsson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):41-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gestalt psychology and the philosophy of mind.William Epstein & Gary Hatfield - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (2):163-181.
    The Gestalt psychologists adopted a set of positions on mind-body issues that seem like an odd mix. They sought to combine a version of naturalism and physiological reductionism with an insistence on the reality of the phenomenal and the attribution of meanings to objects as natural characteristics. After reviewing basic positions in contemporary philosophy of mind, we examine the Gestalt position, characterizing it m terms of phenomenal realism and programmatic reductionism. We then distinguish Gestalt philosophy of mind from instrumentalism and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Behaviorism as the praxist views it.Robert Epstein - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):702-703.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct perception or mediated perception: a comparison of rival viewpoints.William Epstein - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):384-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Trust and the doxastic family.Pascal Engel - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 161 (1):17-26.
    This article examines Keith Lehrer's distinction between belief and acceptance and how it differs from other accounts of belief and of the family of doxastic attitudes. I sketch a different taxonomy of doxastic attitudes. Lehrer's notion of acceptance is mostly epistemic and at the service of his account of the "loop of reason", whereas for other writers acceptance is mostly a pragmatic attitude. I argue, however, that his account of acceptance underdetermines the role that the attitude of trust plays in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Believing, holding true, and accepting.Pascal Engel - 1998 - Philosophical Explorations 1 (2):140 – 151.
    Belief is not a unified phenomenon. In this paper I argue, as a number of other riters argue, that one should distinguish a variety of belief-like attitudes: believing proper - a dispositional state which can have degrees - holding true - which can occur without understanding what one believes - and accepting - a practical and contextual attitude that has a role in deliberation and in practical reasoning. Acceptance itself is not a unified attitude. I explore the various relationships and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Slips of the tongue.Kathleen Emmett - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (2):203-222.
    Abstract Freud's theory of slips of the tongue has been extensively criticized by Adolf Grunbaum and Edward Erwin. They argue that in an effort to make the theory plausible Freud relied on examples of speech errors that do not conform to his theoretical characterization of slips of the tongue. These examples have contributed to the impression that Freud's theory relies on a broader evidential base than it in fact does. Furthermore they argue that Freud has not established the existence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuroscience as a Human Science: Integrating Phenomenology and Empiricism in the Study of Action and Consciousness. [REVIEW]Ralph D. Ellis - 2013 - Human Studies 36 (4):491-507.
    This paper considers where contemporary neuroscience leaves us in terms of how human consciousness fits into the material world, and whether consciousness is reducible to merely mechanical physical systems, or on the contrary whether consciousness is a self-organizing system that can in a sense use the brain for its own purposes. The paper discusses how phenomenology can be integrated with new findings about “neural plasticity” to yield new approaches to the mind–body problem and the place of consciousness as a causal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intentionality and information theory.David P. Ellerman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):143-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Beliefs and responsibility.Carl Elliott - 1991 - Journal of Value Inquiry 25 (3):233-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rationality and the sanctity of competence.Hillel J. Einhorn & Robin M. Hogarth - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):334-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The 'interests' of science and the problems of education.Martin Eger - 1989 - Synthese 80 (1):81 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The body as object versus the body as subject: The case of disability.Steven D. Edwards - 1998 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1 (1):47-56.
    This paper is prompted by the charge that the prevailing Western paradigm of medical knowledge is essentially Cartesian. Hence, illness, disease, disability, etc. are said to be conceived of in Cartesian terms. The paper attempts to make use of the critique of Cartesianism in medicine developed by certain commentators, notably Leder (1992), in order to expose Cartesian commitments in conceptions of disability. The paper also attempts to sketch an alternative conception of disability — one partly inspired by the work of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Observing protocol.Judith Economos - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):677-677.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct awareness and inference.Judith Economos - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):452.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A dualist-interactionist perspective.John C. Eccles - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):430-431.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some philosophical implications of the rehabilitation of group selection.John Dupré - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):619-620.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Subtle ways of shifting the balance in favor of between-group selection.Lee Alan Dugatkin - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):618-619.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Searle's Freudian slip.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):603-604.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stalking intentionality.Fred I. Dretske - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language and the deep unconscious mind: Aspectualities of the theory of syntax.B. Elan Dresher & Norbert Hornstein - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):602-603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious acts and their objects.Fred Dretske - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):676-677.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Personal/Subpersonal Distinction.Zoe Drayson - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (5):338-346.
    Daniel Dennett's distinction between personal and subpersonal explanations was fundamental in establishing the philosophical foundations of cognitive science. Since it was first introduced in 1969, the personal/subpersonal distinction has been adapted to fit different approaches to the mind. In one example of this, the ‘Pittsburgh school’ of philosophers attempted to map Dennett's distinction onto their own distinction between the ‘space of reasons’ and the ‘space of causes’. A second example can be found in much contemporary philosophy of psychology, where Dennett's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Searle’s Answer to ‘Hume’s Problem’.Richard Double - 1984 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (3):435-438.
    John searle has recently claimed to have dissolved what daniel dennett calls 'hume's problem'--The question whether the explanation of behavior by appeal to mental representations can be done without circularity or infinite regress. Searle argues that a careful analysis of the concept of an intentional state shows that mental representations do not require intentional "homunculi" to explain how intentional states have their contents, And, Hence dennett's worry is groundless. I argue that searle's conceptual analysis of intentional states, Even if correct, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Puppeteers, hypnotists, and neurosurgeons.Richard Double - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 56 (June):163-73.
    The objection to R-S accounts that was raised by the possibility of external agents requires the acceptance of two premises, viz., that all R-S accounts allow for puppeteers and that puppeteers necessarily make us unfree. The Metaphilosophical reply shows that to the extent that puppeteers are more problematic than determinism per se, pup-peteers may be explicitly excluded since they violate our paradigm of free will. The Metaphilosophical reply also suggests that we should not expect our mature R-S account to supply (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Libertarianism and Rat ionality.Richard Double - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):431-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • How rational must free will be?Richard Double - 1992 - Metaphilosophy 23 (3):268-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The function and process of perception.Jonathan F. Doner & Joseph S. Lappin - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):383-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can we analyze Skinner's problem-solving behavior in operant terms?P. C. Dodwell - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):592-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark