Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)The virtues of virtual machines.Shannon Densmore & Daniel C. Dennett - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenemenological Research 59 (3):747-61.
    Paul Churchland's book is an entertaining and instructive advertisement for a "neurocomputational" vision of how the brain works. While we agree with its general thrust, and commend its lucid pedagogy on a host of difficult topics, we note that such pedagogy often exploits artificially heightened contrast, and sometimes the result is a misleading caricature instead of a helpful simplification. In particular, Churchland is eager to contrast the explanation of consciousness that can be accomplished by his "aspiring new structural and dynamic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Norton’s Objective Temporal Passage.Kyley Ewing - 2021 - Philosophia 50 (1):65-74.
    This paper considers one unique solution to the puzzle of temporal passage in the block universe. argues that, although a precise description of its workings is currently beyond our understanding, time really passes. After introducing Norton’s account, I argue that it both implies a counterintuitive relationship between the “now” and passage and that it leads to an unlikely relationship between our experience and reality. I then propose that, even if one is willing to accept these consequences, there is reason to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What We Really Know About Consciousness Review of A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness by Bernard Baars. [REVIEW]Bruce Bridgeman - 1995 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 2.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some ethical implications of neurosciences.Charles Susanne & M. Szente - 1997 - Global Bioethics 10 (1-4):111-121.
    The new methods of modern sciences can contribute to understand the genesis of mental illness, the disturbances in brain chemistry, physiology, anatomy or genetical information underlying different diseases of the nervous system. Understanding mental illness is not only challenging to science, but is also of great social importance. Moreover, the new developments of neurosciences put new lights on discussions such as brain-mind concepts, unity of mind, definition of consciousness and even definition of the person.For the majority of the scientists, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Archaeological evidence for mimetic mind and culture.Thomas Wynn - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):774-774.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The “calibration” solution still leaves much work to be done.A. P. Petrov - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):273-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The translation solution plus motion suppression account for perceived stability.Arnold E. Stoper - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):278-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Visual stability: What is new?P. van Donkelaar & U. Windhorst - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):280-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Voluntary oscillopsia: Watching the world go round.J. T. Enright - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):260-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Should we continue to study consciousness?Richard M. Warren - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):270-271.
    Block has attempted to reduce the confusion and controversy concerning the term “consciousness” by suggesting that there are two forms or types of consciousness, each of which has several characteristics or properties. This suggestion appears to further becloud the topic, however. Perhaps consciousness cannot be defined adequately and should not be considered as a topic that can be studied scientifically.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A model devoid of consciousness.Bredo C. Johnsen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):176-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The “Multiple Drafts” model and the ontology of consciousness.Antti Revonsuo - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):177-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ultimate differences.G. Lynn Stephens & George Graham - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):698-699.
    Gray unwisely melds together two distinguishable contributions of consciousness: one to epistemology, the other to evolution. He also renders consciousness needlessly invisible behaviorally.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hunting for consciousness in the brain: What is (the name of) the game?José-Luis Díaz - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):679-680.
    Robust theories concerning the connection between consciousness and brain function should derive not only from empirical evidence but also from a well grounded inind-body ontology. In the case of the comparator hypothesis, Gray develops his ideas relying extensively on empirical evidence, but he bounces irresolutely among logically incompatible metaphysical theses which, in turn, leads him to excessively skeptical conclusions concerning the naturalization of consciousness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Context and consciousness.Colin G. Ellard - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):681-682.
    The commentary argues that we cannot be sure that human consciousness has survival value and that in order to understand the origins and, perhaps, the function of consciousness, we should examine the behavioural and neural precursors to consciousness in nonhumans. An example is given of research on the role of context in decisions regarding fleeing from probable predators in the Mongolian gerbil.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Critical Foundations of the Contextual Theory of Mind.Mr S. A. Orwin O'dowd Antiquarivodamailcoza - unknown
    The contextual mind is found attested in various usages of the term complement, in the background of Kant. The difficulties of Kant's intuitionism are taken up through Quine, but referential opacity is resolved as semantic presence in lived context. A further critique of rationalist linguistics is developed from Jakobson, showing generic functions in thought supporting abstraction, binding and thereby semantic categories. Thus Bolzano's influential philosophy of mathematics and science gives way to a critical view of the ancient heritage acknowledged by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception: Embodiment and Beyond. [REVIEW]Jan Kyrre Berg Olsen Friis - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (4):363-367.
    In this commentary on Don Ihde’s paper “Stretching the in-between: embodiment and beyond” I argue that perceptions and observations are based on tacit frames and these frames are expressed through pre-reflexive intuitions thus giving meaning to the perceived content of observations. However, if the objective or given information in perception is incomplete or missing our brain and nervous system will intuitively and unconsciously fill in the missing information in order to act—these particular pieces of added information may not be relevant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Real Knowledge. The problem of content in neural epistemics.J. J. M. Sleutels - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Robin le poidevin the images of time: An essay on temporal representation.Ian B. Phillips - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (2):439-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is conscious experience established instantaneously? Commentary on J.g. Taylor.Talis Bachmann - 1998 - Consciousness and Cognition 7 (2):149-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When timing the mind should also mind the timing: Biases in the measurement of voluntary actions.Steve Joordens, Marc van Duijn & Thomas M. Spalek - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (2):231-40.
    Trevena and Miller provide further evidence that readiness potentials occur in the brain prior to the time that participants claim to have initiated a voluntary movement, a contention originally forwarded by Libet, Gleason, Wright, and Pearl . In their examination of this issue, though, aspects of their data lead them to question whether their measurement of the initiation of a voluntary movement was accurate. The current article addresses this concern by providing a direct analysis of biases in this task. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Vision, body and interpretation in medical imaging diagnostics.Renzhen Chen & Jan Kyrre Berg Olsen Friis - 2024 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 27 (2):253-266.
    This article explores the profound impact of visualism and visual perception in the context of medical imaging diagnostics. It emphasizes the intricate interplay among vision, embodiment, subjectivity, language, and historicity within the realm of medical science and technology, with a specific focus on image consciousness. The study delves into the role of subjectivity in perception, facilitating the communication of opacity and historicity to the perceiving individual. Additionally, it scrutinizes the image interpretation process, drawing parallels to text interpretation and highlighting the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neural-latency noise places limits on human sensitivity to the timing of events.Kielan Yarrow, Carmen Kohl, Toby Segasby, Rachel Kaur Bansal, Paula Rowe & Derek H. Arnold - 2022 - Cognition 222 (C):105012.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mind outside Brain: a radically non-dualist foundation for distributed cognition.Francis Heylighen & Shima Beigi - 2018 - In J. Adam Carter, Andy Clark, Jesper Kallestrup, S. Orestis Palermos & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Socially Extended Epistemology. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 59-86.
    We approach the problem of the extended mind from a radically non-dualist perspective. The separation between mind and matter is an artefact of the outdated mechanistic worldview, which leaves no room for mental phenomena such as agency, intentionality, or feeling. We propose to replace it by an action ontology, which conceives mind and matter as aspects of the same network of processes. By adopting the intentional stance, we interpret the catalysts of elementary reactions as agents exhibiting desires, intentions, and sensations. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Presentism and the Specious Present: From Temporal Experience to Meta‐Metaphysics.Olla Solomyak - 2019 - Dialectica 73 (1-2):247-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Theory of coordinate transformation by efference copy survives another attack.H. Mittelstaedt - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):269-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comparators, functions, and experiences.Harold Merskey - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):689-690.
    The comparator model is insufficient for three reasons. First, consciousness is involved in the process of comparison as well as in the output. Second, we still do not have enough neurophysiological information to match the events of consciousness, although such knowledge is growing. Third, the anatomical localisation proposed can be damaged bilaterally but consciousness will persist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unitary consciousness requires distributed comparators and global mappings.George N. Reeke - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):693-694.
    Gray, like other recent authors, seeks a scientific approach to consciousness, but fails to provide a biologically convincing description, partly because he implicitly bases his model on a computationalist foundation that embeds the contents of thought in irreducible symbolic representations. When patterns of neural activity instantiating conscious thought are shorn of homuncular observers, it appears most likely that these patterns and the circuitry that compares them with memories and plans should be found distributed over large regions of neocortex.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness does not seem to be linked to a single neural mechanism.Carlo Umiltà & Marco Zorzi - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):701-702.
    On the basis of neuropsychological evidence, it is clear that attention should be given a role in any model of consciousness. What is known about the many instances of dissociation between explicit and implicit knowledge after brain damage suggests that conscious experience might not be linked to a restricted area of the brain. Even if it were true that there is a single brain area devoted to consciousness, the subicular area would seem to be an unlikely possibility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (Even Higher-Order) Intentionality Without Consciousness.Georges Rey - 2008 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 1 (1):51-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The scientific untraceability of phenomenal consciousness.Hilla Jacobson-Horowitz - 2008 - Philosophia 36 (4):509-529.
    It is a common conviction among philosophers who hold that phenomenal properties, qualia, are distinct from any cognitive, intentional, or functional properties, that it is possible to trace the neural correlates of these properties. The main purpose of this paper is to present a challenge to this view, and to show that if “non-cognitive” phenomenal properties exist at all, they lie beyond the reach of neuroscience. In the final section it will be suggested that they also lie beyond the reach (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Challenging the computational metaphor: Implications for how we think.Lynn Andrea Stein - unknown
    This paper explores the role of the traditional computational metaphor in our thinking as computer scientists, its influence on epistemological styles, and its implications for our understanding of cognition. It proposes to replace the conventional metaphor--a sequence of steps--with the notion of a community of interacting entities, and examines the ramifications of such a shift on these various ways in which we think.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness without conflation.Anthony P. Atkinson & Martin Davies - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):248-249.
    Although information-processing theories cannot provide a full explanatory account of P-consciousness, there is less conflation and confusion in cognitive psychology than Block suspects. Some of the reasoning that Block criticises can be interpreted plausibly in the light of a folk psychological view of the relation between P-consciousness and A-consciousness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)The attentional spotlight (dennett and the cog project).Joanna J. Bryson - 2006 - Minds and Machines 16 (1):21-28.
    One of the interesting and occasionally controversial aspects of Dennett’s career is his direct involvement in the scientific process. This article describes some of Dennett’s participation on one particular project conducted at MIT, the building of the humanoid robot named Cog. One of the intentions of this project, not to date fully realized, was to test Dennett’s multiple drafts theory of consciousness. I describe Dennett’s involvement and impact on Cog from the perspective of a graduate student. I also describe the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Discovering the moment of consciousness? I: Bridging techniques at work, & II.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1996 - Philosophical Psychology 9 (2):149-96.
    Abstract Connectionist views in psychology and neuroscience give the impression that there is no one place in the brain into which all information funnels. If these impression are accurate, then we will have great difficulty picking out a point in neuronal or psychological time at which phenomena become conscious. If so, pointing to one place in which we are conscious of a particular event and expecting a psychophysical correlation between qualitative and neural events seems hopeless. In response to this worry, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hunting memes.H. C. Plotkin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):768-769.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On distinguishing phenomenal consciousness from the representational functions of mind.Leonard D. Katz - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):258-259.
    One can share Block's aim of distinguishing “phenomenal” experience from cognitive function and agree with much in his views, yet hold that the inclusion of representational content within phenomenal content, if only in certain spatial cases, obscures this distinction. It may also exclude some modular theories, although it is interestingly suggestive of what may be the limits of the phenomenal penetration of the representational mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Pushing brains: Can cognitive neuroscience provide experimental evidence for brain-mind causation?Martin Kurthen - 2010 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 16 (2):5-22.
    What makes the issue of causal relations between mental and cerebral events so special? And is there experimental evidence from neuroscience for this sort of causation? To answer these questions, the issue of brain-mind causation is considered against the background of the mind-brain problem and the theory of causation in general. Then, one empirical study from cognitive neuroscience is discussed as an example of how the correlations of mental and cerebral events and processes are investigated in current research. From the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phenomenal and attentional consciousness may be inextricable.Adam Morton - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):263-264.
    In common sense consciousness has a fairly determinate content – the (single) way an experience feels, the (single) line of thought being consciously followed. The determinacy of the object may be achieved by linking Block's two concepts, so that as long as we hold on to the determinacy of content we are unable to separate P and A.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • More empirical cases to break the accord of phenomenal and access-consciousness.Talis Bachmann - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):249-251.
    Additional experiments show that P-consciousness and A consciousness can be empirically dissociated for the theoretically so phisticated observer. Phenomenal consciousness can have several degrees that are indirectly measurable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Unmasking multiple drafts.Steven J. Todd - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (4):477-494.
    Any theoretician constructing a serious model of consciousness should carefully assess the details of empirical data generated in the neurosciences and psychology. A failure to account for those details may cast doubt on the adequacy of that model. This paper presents a case in point. Dennett and Kinsbourne's (Dennett, D., & Kinsbourne, M. (1992). Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 183-243) assault on the materialist version of the Cartesian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the signals underlying conscious awareness of action.Sukhvinder S. Obhi, Peggy J. Planetta & Jordan Scantlebury - 2009 - Cognition 110 (1):65-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Calibration models and ecological efference mediation theory: Toward a synthesis of indirect and direct perception theories.Wayne L. Shebilske - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):276-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Brain waves and bridges: Comments on Hardcastle's “discovering the moment of consciousness?“.H. Looren de Jong - 1996 - Philosophical Psychology 9 (2):197 – 209.
    In this comment, a picture of ERP research is sketched that is slightly different from Hardcastle's account, in that it emphasises the functional characterisation of ERP components rather than the neurophysiological connections. It is suggested that selection pressure of ERP work on cognitive and neurophysiological theories and vice versa is a more apt metaphor for intertheoretical relations in this field than explanatory extension. Secondly, it is argued that the temporal characteristics of ERP components do not support Hardcastle's claim that they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The limits of neuropsychological models of consciousness.Max Velmans - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):702-703.
    This commentary elaborates on Gray's conclusion that his neurophysiological model of consciousness might explain how consciousness arises from the brain, but does not address how consciousness evolved, affects behaviour or confers survival value. The commentary argues that such limitations apply to all neurophysiological or other third-person perspective models. To approach such questions the first-person nature of consciousness needs to be taken seriously in combination with third-person models of the brain.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Individual differences in attributional style but not in interoceptive sensitivity, predict subjective estimates of action intention.Tegan Penton, Guillaume L. Thierry & Nick J. Davis - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mythos and logos.John Halverson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):762-762.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is perception isomorphic with neural activity?Alexandre Pouget & Terrence J. Sejnowski - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):274-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychopathology and the discontinuity of conscious experience.David R. Hemsley - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):683-684.
    It is accepted that “primary awareness” may emerge from the integration of two classes of information. It is unclear, however, why this cannot take place within the comparator rather than in conjunction with feedback to the perceptual systems. The model has plausibility in relation to the continuity of conscious experience in the normal waking state and may be extended to encompass certain aspects of the “sense of self” which are frequently disrupted in psychotic patients.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark