Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The definition of art.Thomas Adajian - 2018 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The definition of art is controversial in contemporary philosophy. Whether art can be defined has also been a matter of controversy. The philosophical usefulness of a definition of art has also been debated. -/- Contemporary definitions can be classified with respect to the dimensions of art they emphasize. One distinctively modern, conventionalist, sort of definition focuses on art’s institutional features, emphasizing the way art changes over time, modern works that appear to break radically with all traditional art, the relational properties (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)Music and music education: Theory and praxis for 'making a difference'.Thomas A. Regelski - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (1):7–27.
    The ‘music appreciation as contemplation’ paradigm of traditional aesthetics and music education assumes that music exists to be contemplated for itself. The resulting distantiation of music and music education from life creates a legitimation crisis for music education. Failing to make a noteworthy musical difference for society, a politics of advocacy attempts to justify music education. Praxial theories of music, instead, see music as pragmatically social in origin, meaning, and value. A praxial approach to music education stresses that appreciation is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ellen Dissanayake’s Evolutionary Aesthetic.Stephen J. Davies - 2005 - Biology and Philosophy 20 (2-3):291-304.
    Dissanayake argues that art behaviors – which she characterizes first as patterns or syndromes of creation and response and later as rhythms and modes of mutuality – are universal, innate, old, and a source of intrinsic pleasure, these being hallmarks of biological adaptation. Art behaviors proved to enhance survival by reinforcing cooperation, interdependence, and community, and, hence, became selected for at the genetic level. Indeed, she claims that art is essential to the fullest realization of our human nature. I make (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reflective Ethology, Applied Philosophy, and the Moral Status of Animals.Marc Bekoff & Dale Jamieson - manuscript
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aesthetics and the Containment of Grief.Kathleen Marie Higgins - 2020 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 78 (1):9-20.
    My point of departure is the observation that people ubiquitously turn to aesthetic practices in response to the loss of a loved one. I argue that profound loss catapults the bereaved person into an alternate “world” that differs in marked ways from the world we usually occupy, an alternate world lacking even the basic coherence we need to function. Aesthetic practices facilitate restoration of coherence to our experience, as well as reconnection with the social world and recovery from the breakdown (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aesthetics and the Containment of Grief.Kathleen Marie Higgins - 2020 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 78 (1):9-20.
    My point of departure is the observation that people ubiquitously turn to aesthetic practices in response to the loss of a loved one. I argue that profound loss catapults the bereaved person into an alternate “world” that differs in marked ways from the world we usually occupy, an alternate world lacking even the basic coherence we need to function. Aesthetic practices facilitate restoration of coherence to our experience, as well as reconnection with the social world and recovery from the breakdown (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Do Animals Make Art or the Evolutionary Continuity of Species: A Case for Uniqueness.Jerzy Luty - 2017 - Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies 8 (1):107-116.
    When Władysław Tatarkiewicz wrote that there are only two things that can be said about art: that it is a human activity, not a product of nature, and that it is a conscious activity (or its product), adding that every statement about art different from the ones mentioned above was always finally overthrown (Tatarkiewicz, 1980, p. 37), he probably did not think that the first claim could be questioned by anyone. In the following paper, I will trace the history of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Engineered Niches and Naturalized Aesthetics.Richard A. Richards - 2017 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (4):465-477.
    Recent scientific approaches to aesthetics include evolutionary theories about the origin of art behavior, psychological investigations into human aesthetic experience and preferences, and neurophysiological explorations of the mechanisms underlying art experience. Critics of these approaches argue that they are ultimately irrelevant to a philosophical aesthetics because they cannot help us understand the distinctive conceptual basis and normativity of our art experience. This criticism may seem plausible given the piecemeal nature of these scientific approaches, but a more comprehensive naturalistic framework can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What Is Art Good For? The Socio-Epistemic Value of Art.Aleksandra Sherman & Clair Morrissey - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
    Scientists, humanists, and art lovers alike value art not just for its beauty, but also for its social and epistemic importance; that is, for its communicative nature, its capacity to increase one's self-knowledge and encourage personal growth, and its ability to challenge our schemas and preconceptions. However, empirical research tends to discount the importance of such social and epistemic outcomes of art engagement, instead focusing on individuals' preferences, judgments of beauty, pleasure, or other emotional appraisals as the primary outcomes of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Attempting art: an essay on intention-dependence.Michel-Antoine Xhignesse - 2017 - Dissertation, Mcgill University
    Attempting art: an essay on intention-dependenceIt is a truism among philosophers that art is intention-dependent—that is to say, art-making is an activity that depends in some way on the maker's intentions. Not much thought has been given to just what this entails, however. For instance, most philosophers of art assume that intention-dependence entails concept-dependence—i.e. possessing a concept of art is necessary for art-making, so that what prospective artists must intend is to make art. And yet, a mounting body of anthropological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tool use in Cebus: Its relation to object manipulation, the brain, and ecological adaptations.Suzanne Chevalier-Skolnikoff - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):610-627.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does a Piagetian description work?Leah E. Adams-Curtis - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):588-588.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tools, terms, and telencephalons: Neural correlates of “complex’ and “intelligent” behavior”.Marc Bekoff - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):591-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spontaneous tool use and sensorimotor intelligence in Cebus compared with other monkeys and apes.Suzanne Chevalier-Skolnikoff - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):561-588.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Play, Skill, and the Origins of Perceptual Art.Mohan Matthen - 2015 - British Journal of Aesthetics 55 (2):173-197.
    Art is universal across cultures. Yet, it is biologically expensive because of the energy expended and reduced vigilance. Why do humans make and contemplate it? This paper advances a thesis about the psychological origins of perceptual art. First, it delineates the aspects of art that need explaining: not just why it is attractive, but why fine execution and form—which have to do with how the attraction is achieved—matter over and above attractiveness. Second, it states certain constraints: we need to explain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Expression unleashed: The evolutionary and cognitive foundations of human communication.Christophe Heintz & Thom Scott-Phillips - 2023 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 46:e1.
    Human expression is open-ended, versatile, and diverse, ranging from ordinary language use to painting, from exaggerated displays of affection to micro-movements that aid coordination. Here we present and defend the claim that this expressive diversity is united by an interrelated suite of cognitive capacities, the evolved functions of which are the expression and recognition of informative intentions. We describe how evolutionary dynamics normally leash communication to narrow domains of statistical mutual benefit, and how expression is unleashed in humans. The relevant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • PROJECTA: An Art-Based Tool in Trauma Treatment.Marián López Fernández-Cao, Celia Camilli-Trujillo & Laura Fernández-Escudero - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:568948.
    Artistic images, of a universal nature and validated by global culture, are carriers of an emotional potential that can be used for therapeutic purposes in cultural centers as well as in clinical spaces. Esthetic studies reveal the mobilizing power in their contemplation and the capacity to bring out personal stories with healing potential. The general objective of this paper is to design and validate the PROJECTA instrument, consisting of the therapeutic use of artistic images to approach trauma or difficult conditions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavioral Modernity in Retrospect.Stephen Davies - 2019 - Topoi 40 (1):221-232.
    This paper reviews the debate about behavioral modernity in our species, listing counterexamples to the thesis that there was a dramatic change to the minds of Cro-Magnon sapiens in Europe in the Upper Paleolithic. It is argued that we were probably behaviorally modern from about 150,000 years ago, and that aspects of this mentality were apparent in developments in tool technologies and hunting practices across the prior Homo lineage. Key behaviors expressive of behavioral modernity include practical reasoning about the past (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Recommending beauty: semantics and pragmatics of aesthetic predicates.Ivan Milić & Javier González de Prado Salas - 2018 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 61 (2):198-221.
    The paper offers a semantic and pragmatic analysis of statements of the form ‘x is beautiful’ as involving a double speech act: first, a report that x is beautiful relative to the speaker’s aesthetic standard, along the lines of naive contextualism; second, the speaker’s recommendation that her audience comes to share her appraisal of x as beautiful. We suggest that attributions of beauty tend to convey such a recommendation due to the role that aesthetic practices play in fostering and enhancing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Tool use, imitation, and insight: Apples, oranges, and conceptual pea soup.Dorothy M. Fragaszy - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):596-598.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Literary study and evolutionary theory.Joseph Carroll - 1998 - Human Nature 9 (3):273-292.
    Several recent books have claimed to integrate literary study with evolutionary biology. All of the books here considered, except Robert Storey’s, adopt conceptions of evolutionary theory that are in some way marginal to the Darwinian adaptationist program. All the works attempt to connect evolutionary study with various other disciplines or methodologies: for example, with cultural anthropology, cognitive psychology, the psychology of emotion, neurobiology, chaos theory, or structuralist linguistics. No empirical paradigm has yet been established for this field, but important steps (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolution and literary theory.Joseph Carroll - 1995 - Human Nature 6 (2):119-134.
    Presupposing that all knowledge is the study of a unitary order of nature, the author maintains that the study of literature should be included within the larger field of evolutionary theory. He outlines four elementary concepts in evolutionary theory, and he argues that these concepts should regulate our understanding of literature. On the basis of these concepts, he repudiates the antirealist and irrationalist views that, under the aegis of “poststructuralism,” have dominated academic literary studies for the past two decades. He (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Verse form.John Constable - 1997 - Human Nature 8 (2):171-203.
    This paper presents a pilot study in the "epidemiological" program for cultural research put forward by Dan Sperber. Theory is offered to argue that verse form is so disabling that its worldwide distribution must be explained by functions other than the broad communicative, or ideological, power traditionally attributed to it. The theoretical case is confirmed by numerical data showing that in matched texts of English prose and verse the latter contain words of a lower mean length (measured in syllables). Candidate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kovesi and the Formal and Material Elements of Concepts.T. Brian Mooney, John N. Williams & Mark Nowacki - 2010 - Philosophia 39 (4):699-720.
    In his seminal work Moral Notions , Julius Kovesi presents a novel account of concept formation. At the heart of this account is a distinction between what he terms the material element and the formal element of concepts. This paper elucidates his distinction in detail and contrasts it with other distinctions such as form-matter, universal-particular, genus-difference, necessary-sufficient, and open texture-closed texture. We situate Kovesi’s distinction within his general philosophical method, outlining his views on concept formation in general and explain how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Needs, Creativity, and Care: Adorno and the Future of Work.Craig Reeves & Matthew Sinnicks - 2023 - Organization 30 (5):851–872.
    This paper attempts to show how Adorno’s thought can illuminate our reflections on the future of work. It does so by situating Adorno’s conception of genuine activity in relation to his negativist critical epistemology and his subtle account of the distinction between true and false needs. What emerges is an understanding of work that can guide our aspirations for the future of work, and one we illustrate via discussions of creative work and care work. These are types of work which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Evolutionary Significance of the Arts: Exploring the By-product Hypothesis in the Context of Ritual, Precursors, and Cultural Evolution.Derek Hodgson & Jan Verpooten - 2015 - Biological Theory 10 (1):73-85.
    The role of the arts has become crucial to understanding the origins of “modern human behavior,” but continues to be highly controversial as it is not always clear why the arts evolved and persisted. This issue is often addressed by appealing to adaptive biological explanations. However, we will argue that the arts have evolved culturally rather than biologically, exploiting biological adaptations rather than extending them. In order to support this line of inquiry, evidence from a number of disciplines will be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Using behavior to explain behavior.Marc N. Branch - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):594-595.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Roots and Route of the Artification Hypothesis.Ellen Dissanayake - 2017 - Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies 8 (1):15-32.
    Over four decades, my ideas about the arts in human evolution have themselves evolved, from an original notion of art as a human behaviour of “making special” to a full-fledged hypothesis of artification. A summary of the gradual developmental path (or route) of the hypothesis, based on ethological principles and concepts, is given, and an argument presented in which artification is described as an exaptation whose roots lie in adaptive features of ancestral mother–infant interaction that contributed to infant survival and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Scienticity and Artistry Across All Subjects.Anthony Lock - 2018 - Philosophia 46 (2):355-377.
    Both scienticity and artistry have been listed in cluster concept definitions for both science and art. However, these clusters have not been considered together before. I contrast and combine these different clusters for the first time, and I argue that doing so better elucidates the properties of the natural sciences, humanities and fine arts than the science and art cluster concepts do separately. This is because all disciplines have varying levels of scienticity and artistry, but this is not captured fully (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Music and Music Education: Theory and praxis for ‘making a difference’.Thomas A. Regelski - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (1):7-27.
    The ‘music appreciation as contemplation’ paradigm of traditional aesthetics and music education assumes that music exists to be contemplated for itself. The resulting distantiation of music and music education from life creates a legitimation crisis for music education. Failing to make a noteworthy musical difference for society, a politics of advocacy attempts to justify music education. Praxial theories of music, instead, see music as pragmatically social in origin, meaning, and value. A praxial approach to music education stresses that appreciation is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Artist and the Bengalese Finch.Stephen Davies - 2016 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7 (4):715-720.
    Anjan Chatterjee has promoted an analogy between the Bengalese finch and the human artist. With reduced selective pressure from females due to its domestication, the male finch’s song has become more elaborate. Similarly, art’s lack of a practical function facilitates the creative generativity shown by artists. I argue that this analogy is flawed on both sides. Only recently has some art been regarded as non-functional. And the elaboration of the finch’s song is an effect of female selection under the conditions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Defining Art and Artworlds.Stephen Davies - 2015 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4):375-384.
    Most art is made by people with a well-developed concept of art and who are familiar with its forms and genres as well as with the informal institutions of its presentation and reception. This is reflected in philosophers’ proposed definitions. The earliest artworks were made by people who lacked the concept and in a context that does not resemble the art traditions of established societies, however. An adequate definition must accommodate their efforts. The result is a complex, hybrid definition: something (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Tool use in birds: An avian monkey wrench?Irene M. Pepperberg - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):604-605.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Does “spontaneous” behavior require “cognitive special creation”?John D. Baldwin - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):589-590.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Experimental mood manipulation does not induce change in preference for natural landscapes.Bernadette Klopp & Linda Mealey - 1998 - Human Nature 9 (4):391-399.
    According to evolutionary theory, emotions are psychological mechanisms that have evolved to enhance fitness in specific situations by motivating appropriate (adaptive) behavior. Taking this perspective, a previous study examined the relationship between mood and preference for natural environments. It reported that participants’ anxiety level was associated with a preference for landscapes offering what Appleton called "refuge," while participants’ anger and cheerfulness were both associated with a preference for landscapes offering what Appleton called "prospect." We attempted to replicate these results and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tool use in monkeys.Sue Savage-Rumbaugh, Karen Brakke & Krista Wilkinson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):606-607.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the contents of capuchins' cognitive toolkit.James R. Anderson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):588-589.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Aesthetic Primitives”: Fundamental Biological Elements of a Naturalistic Aesthetics.Ellen Dissanayake - 2015 - Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 8 (1):6-24.
    Aesthetics, like other philosophical subjects, has historically made use of «top down» methods. Recent discoveries in genetics, evolutionary psychology, paleoarchaeology, and neuroscience call for a new «naturalistic» or «bottom up» perspective. Combining these fields with behavioral biology and ethnoarts studies, I offer seven premises that underlie a new understanding of evolved predispositions of the brain/mind that all artists use to attract attention, sustain interest, and create, mold, and shape emotion. I describe aesthetic «primitives» in somatic and behavioral modalities, suggesting that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Making «art» in Prehistory: signs and figures of metaphorical paleolithic man.Fabio Martini - 2015 - Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 8 (1):41-52.
    We owe our first graphic experiences to Neanderthal Man, who introduced to the cultural baggage of the genus Homo two metaphorical behaviors that are fundamental in terms of their innovation: one concerns the preservation of the bodies of the dead through burial, the other is the making of signs, which in this stage of evolution do not yet represent recognizable subjects but only lines. This attests to the creation of a graphical tool that materializes and makes visible that which exists (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cebus uses tools, but what about representation? Comparative evidence for generalized cognitive structures.Patricia M. Greenfield - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):599-600.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Art and Spirit: The Artistic Brain, the Navajo Concept of Hozho, and Kandinsky’s “Inner Necessity ”.Charles D. Laughlin - 2004 - International Journal of Transpersonal Studies 23 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Using art history and philosophy to compare a traditional and a contemporary form of african moral thought.Parker English & Nancy Steele Hamme - 1996 - Journal of Social Philosophy 27 (2):204-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Advanced sensorimotor intelligence in Cebus and Macaca.Gregory Charles Westergaard & Gene P. Sackett - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):609-610.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ¿Qué es el arte y qué constituye el valor artístico?Jordi Tena Sánchez & Indira Centellas - 2022 - Pensamiento. Revista de Investigación E Información Filosófica 78 (297):199-228.
    El presente artículo se basa en la teoría de la creatividad artística de Jon Elster para tratar de ofrecer un esbozo de definición del concepto de arte, así como las bases para una teoría del valor artístico. Se sostiene que una obra de arte es una creación humana realizada con la intención de provocar una experiencia estética, así como que el principal valor de una obra de arte radica en su capacidad para producir emociones estéticas y no estéticas. Dicha concepción (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The applicability of Piagetian concepts to animals.Adriaan Kortlandt - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):601-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Primate tool use: Parsimonious explanations make better science.Elisabetta Visalberghi - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):608-609.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tool use in cebus monkeys: Moving from orthodox to neo-Piagetian analyses.Kathleen R. Gibson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):598-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Imitation and derivative reactions.Sue Taylor Parker - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):604-604.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Biobehavioural basis of art.R. F. Harle - 2009 - Technoetic Arts 6 (3):259-268.
    This paper argues that the human activity of art making and art usage has a biological foundation which precedes language acquisition. Together with cultural dynamics we have created ourselves as we have created our arts. I attempt a synthesis of the theories of Dissanayake and Joyce which shows the human trait of art behaviour evolved as surely as did the behaviours of mating and hunting.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognition as cause.Michael Tomasello - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):607-608.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark