Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Intuition, competence, and performance.Henry E. Kyburg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):341-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Rationality is a necessary presupposition in psychology.Jan Smedslund - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):352-352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge, Society, and History.Philip Kitcher - 1993 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):155 - 177.
    Here is a traditional way of thinking about human knowledge. Knowledge is a species of true belief. The crucial difference between knowledge and other kinds of true belief is that propositions that are known have a special property. Justified propositions either have intrinsic justification or else they are obtainable by means of a justification-conferring argument from other justified propositions that the knower believes. The only propositions with intrinsic justification are those that fall into one of two classes: the set of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Disjunction.Ray Jennings - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quine on theory and language.Nobuharu Tanji - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (2):233-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconsidering Devitt on Realism and Truth.Michael Gifford - 2019 - Erkenntnis 86 (6):1367-1380.
    Michael Devitt tells us that metaphysical realism has a kind of immunity from considerations concerning the nature of truth. Part of this immunity comes from Devitt’s insistence that realism is a metaphysical issue, not a semantic one. Most of Devitt’s critics have focused on this point, arguing that a proper understanding of the realism question necessarily involves semantic considerations :65–74, 1991; Miller in Synthese 136:191–217, 2003; Putnam in Comments on Michael Devitt’s ‘Hilary and Me’, in: Baghramian Reading Putnam. Taylor and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The case for widespread simultaneous causation.Cei Maslen - 2018 - Philosophical Quarterly 68 (270):123-137.
    In this paper, I examine recent arguments for the widespread existence of simultaneous causation from Huemer & Kovitz and Mumford & Anjum, and conclude that they are mistaken. I argue that these arguments overlook two pictures of causation which are commonly assumed, which I call the Standard Modern Picture and the Contiguous Extended Picture.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Analytic Philosophy and its Synoptic Commission: Towards the Epistemic End of Days.Fraser MacBride - 2014 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 74:221-236.
    There is no such thing as , conceived as a special discipline with its own distinctive subject matter or peculiar method. But there is an analytic task for philosophy that distinguishes it from other reflective pursuits, a global or synoptic commission: to establish whether the final outputs of other disciplines and common sense can be fused into a single periscopic vision of the Universe. And there is the hard-won insight that thought and language aren't transparent but stand in need of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Should Bayesians sometimes neglect base rates?Isaac Levi - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):342-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Antirealism and constructivism: Brouwer’s weak counterexamples: Antirealism and constructivism: Brouwer’s weak counterexamples.Charles Mccarty - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):147-159.
    Strictly intuitionistic inferences are employed to demonstrate that three conditions—the existence of Brouwerian weak counterexamples to _Test_, the recognition condition, and the _BHK_ interpretation of the logical signs—are together inconsistent. Therefore, if the logical signs in mathematical statements governed by the recognition condition are constructive in that they satisfy the clauses of the _BHK_, then every relevant instance of the classical principle _Test_ is true intuitionistically, and the antirealistic critique of conventional logic, once thought to yield such weak counterexamples, is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Brouwer’s weak counterexamples and testability: Further remarks: Brouwer’s weak counterexamples and testability: Further remarks.Charles Mccarty - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):513-523.
    Straightforwardly and strictly intuitionistic inferences show that the Brouwer– Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation, in the presence of a formulation of the recognition principle, entails the validity of the Law of Testability: that the form ¬ f V ¬¬ f is valid. Therefore, the BHK and recognition, as described here, are inconsistent with the axioms both of intuitionistic mathematics and of Markovian constructivism. This finding also implies that, if the BHK and recognition are suitably formulated, then Brouwer’s original weak counterexample reasoning was fallacious. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frege, Perry, and Demonstratives.Palle Yourgrau - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (4):725 - 752.
    'You ask me about the idiosyncrasies of philosophers? There is their lack of historical sense, their hatred of even the idea of becoming, their Egyptianism. They think they are doing a thing honour when they dehistoricize it, sub specie aeternitatis — when they make a mummy of it.'Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Language, Partial Truth, and Logic. [REVIEW]C. Z. Elgin - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):313-322.
    In Hard Truths, Elijah Millgram maintains that analytic philosophy rests on a mistake. 1 It is committed to bivalence – the contention that every truth bearer is either true or false. As a result of this commitment, its views about logic and metaphysics are profoundly misguided. He believes that rather than restricting ourselves to two truth values, we should recognize a plethora of partial truths – sentences, beliefs and opinions that are partly true or true in a way. These are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction.Agustin Rayo & Gabriel Uzquiano - 2006 - In Agustín Rayo & Gabriel Uzquiano (eds.), Absolute generality. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Whether or not we achieve absolute generality in philosophical inquiry, most philosophers would agree that ordinary inquiry is rarely, if ever, absolutely general. Even if the quantifiers involved in an ordinary assertion are not explicitly restricted, we generally take the assertion’s domain of discourse to be implicitly restricted by context.1 Suppose someone asserts (2) while waiting for a plane to take off.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Weyl on sets and abstraction.Stephen Pollard - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 53 (1):131 - 140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Frege in context. [REVIEW]Nikolay Milkov - 2001 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3):557 – 570.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Truth and the Enigma of Knowability.Bernhard Weiss - 2007 - Dialectica 61 (4):521-537.
    Since its disc overy by Fitch, the paradox of knowability has been a thorn in the anti‐realist's side. Recently both Dummett and Tennant have sought to relieve the anti‐realist by restricting the applicability of the knowability principle – the principle that all truths are knowable – which has been viewed as both a cardinal doctrine of anti‐realism and the assumption for reductio of Fitch's argument. In this paper it is argued that the paradox of knowability is a peculiarly acute manifestation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Is” and “ought” in cognitive science.William G. Lycan - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):344-345.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The irrational, the unreasonable, and the wrong.Avishai Margalit & Maya Bar-Hillel - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):346-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On defining rationality unreasonably.J. St B. T. Evans & P. Pollard - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):335-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Another vote for rationality.Mary Henle - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):339-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Trusting our own minds.Dennis Kalde - 2019 - Dissertation, Ludwig Maximilians Universität, München
    When it comes to the metaethical task of explaining and making sense of what it is that we are doing while doing ethics, the subject of moral objectivity occupies an important and special place within that task. Thus, it is often agreed that being able to explain and justify the objective features of common moral practice is one of if not the most important task for any metaethical theory to undertake. In this dissertation, I tackle the issue of ethical objectivity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human rationality: Misleading linguistic analogies.Geoffrey Sampson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):350-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some questions regarding the rationality of a demonstration of human rationality.Robert J. Sternberg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):352-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Can realism be naturalised? Putnam on sense, Commonsense, and the senses.Chistopher Norris - 2000 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 4 (1):89-140.
    Hilary Putnam has famously undergone some radical changes of mind with regard to the issue of scientific realism and its wider epistemological bearings. In this paper I defend the arguments put forward by early Putnam in his essays on the causal theory of reference as applied to natural-kind terms, despite his own later view that those arguments amounted to a form of 'metaphysical' realism which could not be sustained against various lines of sceptical attack. I discuss some of the reasons (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond the axioms: The question of objectivity in mathematics.W. TaitW - 2001 - Philosophia Mathematica 9 (1):21-36.
    This paper contains a defense against anti-realism in mathematics in the light both of incompleteness and of the fact that mathematics is a ‘cultural artifact.’. Anti-realism (here) is the view that theorems, say, of aritltmetic cannot be taken at face value to express true propositions about the system of numbers but must be reconstrued to be about somctliiiig else or about nothing at all. A ‘bite-the-bullet’ aspect of the defease is that, adopting new axioms, liitherto independent, is not. a matter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Theorizing About Theories and Mathematical Existence.J. L. Usó-Doménech, J. A. Nescolarde-Selva & H. Gash - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (3):587-595.
    Suppes proposes an analysis of the structure and identity of empirical theories with his model-theoretical approach and undertakes effective reconstructions of theories in diverse disciplinary fields. Here the authors analyse the results of these examinations under the optics of questions concerning the assumed ontological commitments, and for how they satisfy economic and other criteria.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What Strong Sociologists can Learn from Critical Realism: Bloor on the History of Aerodynamics.Christopher Norris - 2014 - Journal of Critical Realism 13 (1):3-37.
    This essay presents a long, detailed, in many ways critical but also appreciative account, of David Bloor’s recent book The Enigma of the Aerofoil. I take that work as the crowning statement of ideas and principles developed over the past four decades by Bloor and other exponents of the ‘strong programme’ in the sociology of scientific knowledge. It therefore offers both a test-case of that approach and a welcome opportunity to review, clarify and extend some of the arguments brought against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Post-Tarskian Truth.Jaakko Hintikka - 2001 - Synthese 126 (1-2):17-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Philosophy of the Subject: back to the future.Jim Mackenzie - 1998 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 30 (2):135-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Realism and nursing.Trevor Hussey - 2000 - Nursing Philosophy 1 (2):98-108.
    It is argued that philosophical realism is well suited to serve as a perspective from which to understand nursing, and that it should be considered as an alternative to positivist, interpretivist, hermeneutical and phenomenological approaches. However, existing forms of realism, including theory and entity realism are shown to be faced with serious problems. In response, an alternative form ‘constraint realism’ is outlined, and shown to be apposite for illuminating the rule or convention governed behaviour characteristic of human beings. A brief (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Philosophy and Machine Learning.Paul Thagard - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):261-276.
    Philosophers since the ancient Greeks have investigated the nature of different kinds of inference. Although deductive inference in the form of Aristotelian syllogisms and Fregean formal logic has predominated, much attention has also been paid to induction, inference where the conclusion does not follow necessarily from the premises.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)On identifying the mental with the physical.Peter Smith - 1983 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (June):227-238.
    Our states of belief and desire are no doubt supervenient on the overall pattern of our physical states. But can this minimal physicalist presumption be strengthened into a claim to the effect that our mental states are each identical with some specific corresponding physical state? A developed identity theory will need, in a sense to be made clear, a schema for specifying the physical state which is supposed to be identical with a given mental state. And there are problems in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sobre las nociones de lógica y argumento de John Stuart Mill.Xavier De Donato Rodríguez - 2015 - Télos 20 (1):51-68.
    My aim in this paper is to discuss Mill’s notions of logic and argument and to highlight the epistemic dimension that for Mill has every argument and that, it is in the light of this epistemic dimension, that an argument should be assessed. By taking into account these considerations, I focus on his criticism against deductive arguments to the effect that they commit the fallacy of begging the question. I try to show that this idea relies on his radical empiricism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Performing competently.Lola L. Lopes - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):343-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Formulating a plausible relativism.Steve Edwards - 1993 - Philosophia 22 (1-2):63-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rationality and the sanctity of competence.Hillel J. Einhorn & Robin M. Hogarth - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):334-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dancing Chief in the Brain or Consciousness as an Entanglement.Yukio-Pegio Gunji & Kyoko Nakamura - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (1):151-184.
    Free will in intentional consciousness is exposed to skeptics since it was found that subconscious neural activities, what is called readiness potential, precedes the intention to an action. The question of whether free will is an authentic illusion has been argued not only in psychology but physics and philosophy. Most of scientists, however, think that the intentional consciousness who believes to have his/her own free will, is determined by readiness potential in advance, and that free will cannot coexist with determinism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can any statements about human behavior be empirically validated?Baruch Fischoff - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):336-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Paradox of Conceptualizability. [REVIEW]Nikolaj Jang Lee Linding Pedersen - 2020 - Philosophia 49 (2):555-563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can children's irrationality be experimentally demonstrated?Sam Glucksberg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):337-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark