Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Mathematics: Felix Mühlhölzer in Conversation with Sebastian Grève.Felix Mühlhölzer - 2014 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 3 (2):151-180.
    Sebastian Grève interviews Felix Mühlhölzer on his work on the philosophy of mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From What Can’t be Said To What Isn’t Known.Christine McKinnon - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):87-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical reasons.Pascal Engel - 2005 - Philosophical Explorations 8 (1):21 – 38.
    Simon Blackburn has shown that there is an analogy between the problem of moral motivation in ethics (how can moral reasons move us?) and the problem of what we might call the power of logical reasons (how can logical reasons move us, what is the force of the 'logical must?'). In this paper, I explore further the parallel between the internalism problem in ethics and the problem of the power of logical reasons, and defend a version of psychologism about reasons, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and Idealism.Bernard Williams - 1973 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 7:76-95.
    Tractatus, 5.62 famously says: ‘… what the solipsist means is quite correct; only it cannot be said but makes itself manifest. The world is my world: this is manifest in the fact that the limits of language mean the limits of my world.’ The later part of this repeats what was said in summary at 5.6: ‘the limits of my language mean the limits of my world’. And the key to the problem ‘how much truth there is in solipsism’ has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Los conceptos abierLos Y la paradoja Del análisis (open concepts and the paradox of analysis).Sílvio Pinto - 2005 - Theoria 20 (2):199-219.
    Michael Beaney ha sugerido recientemente que la distinción fregeana entre sentido y referencia fue propuesta para resolver la famosa paradoja del análisis. Casi diez años antes, Michael Dummett ya insistia en que Frege fue uno de los prirneros en buscar una soluci6n satisfactoria de esta paradoja. En esre articulo, discuto algunas sugerencias de Beaney y Dummett de cómo resolver la paradoja al estilo fregeano y tarnbién sus propias contribuciones no fregeanas al debate en torno de la corrección y de la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hinter das Bewusstsein zurück: Implizites Wissen als Ansatzpunkt der Sozialontologie.Stephan Zimmermann - 2020 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 68 (6):848-866.
    The state of recent as well as older research on social ontology suggests a paradigmatic approach, according to which it is our consciousness that must provide the framework for conceptualising the social. I, however, argue that Wittgenstein’s treatment of rule-following opens up a new horizon for the ontology of the social. The fact that the rules of our language are social in nature and that we need not be aware of them in order to follow them shifts the problem to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Reference to Perfect Numbers in Plato’s Theaetetus.F. Acerbi - 2005 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 59 (4):319-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • El nihilismo modal frente al argumento de McFretidge a favor de la necesidad de la creencia en la necesidad.José Edgar González Varela - 2013 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 45 (1):269-298.
    En este trabajo examino el argumento de McFetridge a favor de la necesidad de la creencia en la necesidad. El argumento pretende establecer un dilema fatal para el “nihilista” modal, aquel que no cree que al menos alguna proposición es necesaria. Mi objetivo principal es mostrar que el dilema que presenta el argumento de McFetridge no es sólido, pues tiene una limitación muy importante con respecto al segundo de sus cuernos, el cual es el más interesante. El segundo cuerno del (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On some standard objections to mathematical conventionalism.Severin Schroeder - 2017 - Belgrade Philosophical Annual 30 (30):83-98.
    According to Wittgenstein, mathematical propositions are rules of grammar, that is, conventions, or implications of conventions. So his position can be regarded as a form of conventionalism. However, mathematical conventionalism is widely thought to be untenable due to objections presented by Quine, Dummett and Crispin Wright. It has also been argued that only an implausibly radical form of conventionalism could withstand the critical implications of Wittgenstein’s rule-following considerations. In this article I discuss those objections to conventionalism and argue that none (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From What Can't Be Said to What Isn't Known.Christine McKinnon - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):87-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Critical Notice.Fred Wilson - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (3):377-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and logic.Montgomery Link - 2009 - Synthese 166 (1):41-54.
    In his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951) presents the concept of order in terms of a notational iteration that is completely logical but not part of logic. Logic for him is not the foundation of mathematical concepts but rather a purely formal way of reflecting the world that at the minimum adds absolutely no content. Order for him is not based on the concepts of logic but is instead revealed through an ideal notational series. He states that logic is “transcendental”. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein, Quine and Dummett on Conventionalism about Logic.Alexander Miller - 2014 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):292-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW]Victor Rodych - 1995 - Philosophia Mathematica 3 (3):271-288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paradigms and incommensurability.Derek L. Phillips - 1975 - Theory and Society 2 (1):37-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics. [REVIEW]Charles McCarty - 1981 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 14 (1):165-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Origins of Analytical Philosophy. [REVIEW]Fred Wilson - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (3):377-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Motivating Wittgenstein's Perspective on Mathematical Sentences as Norms.Simon Friederich - 2011 - Philosophia Mathematica 19 (1):1-19.
    The later Wittgenstein’s perspective on mathematical sentences as norms is motivated for sentences belonging to Hilbertian axiomatic systems where the axioms are treated as implicit definitions. It is shown that in this approach the axioms are employed as norms in that they function as standards of what counts as using the concepts involved. This normative dimension of their mode of use, it is argued, is inherited by the theorems derived from them. Having been motivated along these lines, Wittgenstein’s perspective on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Facts and figures.J. D. Moore - 1969 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (2):145 – 160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intuitionist logic, a logic of justification.John T. Kearns - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (3):243 - 260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark