Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Pragmatism and philosophy of science: A critical survey.Robert Almeder - 2007 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21 (2):171 – 195.
    After delineating the distinguishing features of pragmatism, and noting the resources that pragmatists have available to respond effectively as pragmatists to the two major objections to pragmatism, I examine and critically evaluate the various proposals that pragmatists have offered as a solution to the problem of induction, followed by a discussion of the pragmatic positions on the status of theoretical entities. Thereafter I discuss the pragmatic posture toward the nature of explanation in science. I conclude that pragmatism has (a) a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Illusory Signs as Frustrated Expectations: Undoing Descartes’ Overblown Response.Marc Champagne - 2023 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 79 (3):1073-1096.
    Descartes held that it is impossible to make true statements about what we perceive, but I go over alleged cases of illusory experience to show why such a skeptical conclusion (and recourse to God) is overblown. The overreaction, I contend, stems from an insufficient awareness of the habitual expectations brought to any given experience. These expectations manifest themselves in motor terms, as perception constantly prompts and updates an embodied posture of readiness for what might come next. Such habitual anticipations work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Delirio como creencia.Guillermo Ruiz-Pérez - 2022 - Culturas Cientificas 3 (2):78-108.
    A lo largo de la tradición psicopatológica, incluso de la pre-fenomenológica, se encuentra la categorización del delirio como creencia. Jaspers asumió ese uso y lo fundó fenomenológico-existencialmente, definiendo su carácter de convicción. El concepto de creencia ha tenido un largo recorrido dentro de la historia del pensamiento, aunque recientemente se ha intensificado el debate acerca de la visión doxástica del delirio. En virtud de lo ya mencionado, en el presente artículo presentamos un análisis conceptual de la creencia, con el objetivo (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Réponses à Claudia Cristalli, Olivier Tinland et Louis Quéré.Mathias Girel - 2022 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 14 (2).
    Je suis très sensible à l’honneur qui m’est fait de discuter L’esprit en acte. Psychologie, mythologies et pratique chez les pragmatistes, dans ces colonnes, comme à la qualité des remarques auxquelles je réponds. Avant d’entrer dans le détail, il ne me semble pas inutile de donner deux éléments de situation, qui peuvent aider à préciser quelle place occupe ce livre à mes yeux. §1. L’esprit en acte procède par essais, qui peuvent être lus indépendamment les uns des autres. Il a, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Age of Methods: William Whewell, Charles Peirce, and Scientific Kinds.Henry M. Cowles - 2016 - Isis 107 (4):722-737.
    For William Whewell and, later, Charles Peirce, the methods of science merited scientific examination themselves. Looking to history to build an inductive account of the scientific process, both men transformed scientific methods into scientific evidence. What resulted was a peculiar instance of what Ian Hacking calls “the looping effects of human kinds,” in which classifying human behavior changes that behavior. In the cases of Whewell and Peirce, the behavior in question was their own: namely, scientific study. This essay brings Hacking’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Science, Religion, and “The Will to Believe".Alexander Klein - 2015 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 5 (1):72-117.
    Do the same epistemic standards govern scientific and religious belief? Or should science and religion operate in completely independent epistemic spheres? Commentators have recently been divided on William James’s answer to this question. One side depicts “The Will to Believe” as offering a separate-spheres defense of religious belief in the manner of Galileo. The other contends that “The Will to Believe” seeks to loosen the usual epistemic standards so that religious and scientific beliefs can both be justified by a unitary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Logic, Ethics and Aesthetics.Vitaly Kiryushchenko - 2011 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 3 (2):258-274.
    The relationship between logic and ethics is one of the basic and most essential questions of classical philosophical analysis. Since the time of the Pythagoreans, the fundamental unity of the two – whether by means of vague intuition, an elaborate conceptual scheme, or even a carefully crafted lifestyle – has led philosophers to identify truth and virtue. In his critical philosophy Kant put this unity of truth and virtue to extensive and rigorous trial to determine what conditions, if any, a...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Instability and uneasiness in Hume's theories of belief and justification.Louirs E. Loeb - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (2):301 – 327.
    (1995). Instability and uneasiness in Hume's theories of belief and justification. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 3, No. 2, pp. 301-327.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Belief in Naturalism: an Epistemologist’s Philosophy of Mind.Susan Haack - 2010 - Logos and Episteme 1 (1):67-83.
    My title, “Belief in Naturalism,” signals, not that I adopt naturalism as an article of faith, but that my purpose in this paper is to shed some light on what belief is, on why the concept of belief is needed in epistemology, and how all this relates to debates about epistemological naturalism. After clarifying the many varieties of naturalism, philosophical and other (section 1), and then the various forms of epistemological naturalism specifically (section 2), I offer a theory of belief (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Charles Sanders Peirce 1839–1914.Vincent G. Potter - 1985 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 19:21-41.
    I am honoured and pleased to address you this evening on the life and work of an extraordinary American thinker, Charles Sanders Peirce. Although Peirce is perhaps most often remembered as the father of the philosophical movement known as pragmatism, I would like to impress upon you that he was also, and perhaps, especially, a logician, a working scientist and a mathematician. During his life time Peirce most often referred to himself, and was referred to by his colleagues, as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modest Neural Truths: Dispositions and Foraging for Coherence.Jay Schulkin & Tibor Solymosi - 2023 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 37 (2):137-164.
    William James’s lead continues to provide a balancing act of inquiry and truth with plurality and conflict. First, this article considers this balancing act in neuroscience, both what we have been learning since James published The Principles of Psychology and in how neuroscience is done. As pragmatists have long argued against dualisms and absolutes, the authors situate contemporary understanding in its historical context. Humans have evolved as brains-in-bodies-in-cultures and navigate such worlds through good-enough strategies, not a disembodied reason. Embodied intelligence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skinner: From Essentialist to Selectionist Meaning.Roy A. Moxley - 1997 - Behavior and Philosophy 25 (2):95 - 119.
    Skinner has been criticized for advancing essentialist interpretations of meaning in which meaning is treated as the property of a word or a grammatical form. Such a practice is consistent with a "words and things" view that sought to advance an ideal language as well as with S-R views that presented meaning as the property of a word form. These views imply an essentialist theory of meaning that would be consistent with Skinner's early S-R behaviorism. However, Skinner's more developed account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pluralism and Perspectivism in the American Pragmatist Tradition.Matthew Brown - 2019 - In Michela Massimi (ed.), Knowledge From a Human Point of View. Springer Verlag.
    This chapter explores perspectivism in the American Pragmatist tradition. On the one hand, the thematization of perspectivism in contemporary epistemology and philosophy of science can benefit from resources in the American Pragmatist philosophical tradition. On the other hand, the Pragmatists have interesting and innovative, pluralistic views that can be illuminated through the lens of perspectivism. I pursue this inquiry primarily through examining relevant sources from the Pragmatist tradition. I will illustrate productive engagements between pragmatism and perspectivism in three areas: in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Habit Beyond Psychology.Aleksandar Feodorov - 2017 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 9 (1).
    In the following text I reexamine the connotations of the term habit from the perspective of Peirce’s pragmatism. I start by tracing back the roots of the term in the Metaphysical Club’s discussions of Alexander Bain’s theory of belief. By stressing the relative overlap between belief and habit I am also proposing that the latter term transcends the boundaries of empirical psychology. Peirce’s well-known antipathy to psychologism in logic raised the status of habit to a universal concept that participates in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Belief As a Disposition to Act: Variations on a Pragmatist Theme.Pascal Engel - unknown
    In this paper I want to show that, although it is a common thread of many pragmatist or pragmatist-inspired doctrines, the belief-as-disposition-to-act theme is played on very different tunes by the various philosophical performers. A whole book could be devoted to the topic. I shall limit myself here to the views of Peirce, James, Ramsey, contemporary functionalists, and Isaac Levi. Depending on how they interpret this theme, the pragmatist philosophers can emphasise more or less the role of theory and practice (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Does Continuity Allow For Emergence?Maria Regina Brioschi - 2019 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 11 (2).
    The present paper proposes an emergentist reading of Peirce, with special reference to his concept of evolution. Although the author never adopts the word “emergence” in a technical manner, it will be demonstrated that the core problem of emergence lies at the heart of his evolutionary doctrine, generally displayed by the interplay of his three well-known categories of Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness. Indeed, although the Classical pragmatists most quoted in connection to emergentism are Dewey and Mead (and William James to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Pragmatisme: une philosophie pour philosophes?Claudia Cristalli - 2022 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 14 (2).
    L’esprit en acte se présente comme une réflexion philosophique sur le pragmatisme classique. Dans ce livre, qui peut être lu avec autant d’intérêt par des étudiants en Master que par des spécialistes, Girel reconfigure le tableau pragmatiste à travers une interprétation qui met au centre “le lien entre nos croyances et notre conduite” (2021: 9). Ce livre présente une perspective sur la philosophie de l’esprit qui met l’action et la pratique au centre du discours, grâce à une lecture philosoph...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Charles Sanders Peirce 1839–1914.Vincent G. Potter - 1985 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 19:21-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pragmaticism.Charles S. Peirce - 2024 - De Gruyter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historical and Philosophical Stances.David L. Marshall - 2016 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 8 (2).
    This article explores the intellectual life of Max Harold Fisch, the twentieth-century American scholar of Giambattista Vico and Charles S. Peirce. Fisch was a thinker with fundamental commitments to both history and philosophy. The claim here is that his life exemplifies a constitutive tension in the work of intellectual historians, who operate in the interstice between these two disciplines. What we learn is that intellectual historians may have a double investment both in the filigree of particular historical contexts and in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pursuing Peirce.Joseph Brent - 1996 - Synthese 106 (3):301 - 322.
    Charles S. Peirce, polymath, philosopher, logician, lived a life of often wild extremes and, when he died in 1914, had earned a vile reputation as a debauched genius. Yet he created a unified, profound and brilliant work, both published and unpublished, a fact difficult to explain. In my 1993 biography, I proposed three hypotheses to account for his Jekyll-Hyde character: his obsession with the puzzle of meaning, two neurological pathologies, trigeminal neuralgia and left-handedness, and the powerful influence of his father. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Duas Genealogias da Ação no Pragmatismo.Russell B. Goodman - 2007 - Cognitio 8 (2):213-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Peirce on the passions: The role of instinct, emotion, and sentiment in inquiry and action.Robert J. Beeson - unknown
    One of the least explored areas of C.S. Peirce's wide range of work is his contributions to psychology and the philosophy of mind. This dissertation examines the corpus of this work, especially as it relates to the subjects of mind, habit, instinct, sentiment, emotion, perception, consciousness, cognition, and community. The argument is that Peirce's contributions to these areas of investigation were both highly original and heavily influenced by the main intellectual currents of his time. An effort has been made to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark