Switch to: References

Citations of:

A philosopher's coming of age: A study in erotetic intellectual history

In Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. Clarendon Press. pp. 31--66 (1991)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Different Experimental Lives: Michael Faraday and William Sturgeon.Iwan Rhys Morus - 1992 - History of Science 30 (1):1-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Different Experimental Lives: Michael Faraday and William Sturgeon.Iwan Rhys Morus - 1992 - History of Science 30 (1):1-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Rethinking Whewell.John Wettersten - 1993 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 23 (4):481-515.
    The nineteenth-century appraisal of Whewell's philosophy as confused, eclectic, and metaphysical is still dominant today. Yet he keeps reappearing on the agenda of the historians and philosophers of science. Why? Whewell continues to be a puzzle. Historians evade the puzzle by deeming him to have had no serious philosophy but some interesting ideas and/or to have been socially important. Menachim Fisch's recent study offers promise of a new appraisal. But Fisch's account leads back to the puzzle. Fisch poses the question (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Discoverers' induction.Laura J. Snyder - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):580-604.
    In this paper I demonstrate that, contrary to the standard interpretations, William Whewell's view of scientific method is neither that of the hypothetico-deductivist nor that of the retroductivist. Rather, he offers a unique inductive methodology, which he calls "discoverers' induction." After explicating this methodology, I show that Kepler's discovery of his first law of planetary motion conforms to it, as Whewell claims it does. In explaining Whewell's famous phrase about "happy guesses" in science, I suggest that Whewell intended a distinction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Hegel and Peircean abduction.Paul Redding - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):295–313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ways of knowing: towards a historical sociology of science, technology and medicine.John V. Pickstone - 1993 - British Journal for the History of Science 26 (4):433-458.
    Among the many groups of scholars whose work now illuminates science, technology and medicine (STM), historians, it seems to me, have a key responsibility not just to elucidate change but to establish and explain variety. One of the big pictures we need is a model of the varieties of STM over time; one which does not presume the timeless existence of disciplines, or the distinctions between science, technology and medicine; a model which is both synchronic and diachronic, and both cognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Victorian Piety practiced.Michael O'brien - 2008 - Modern Intellectual History 5 (1):153-163.
    For some time, there has been reason for imagining that we live in neo-Victorian times. We are awash in restless evangelicals, profligate of stern and apocalyptic advice. We have had praying leaders who imagine that foreigners, usually with beards, require reform and invasion. Celts threaten secession and the Union is extolled. There is much talk of families, education, and the anxieties of class. Our novels grow long and vexed, and even have plots. Historians seek the common reader and write meandering (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quantitative realizations of philosophy of science: William Whewell and statistical methods.Kent Johnson - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (3):399-409.
    In this paper, I examine William Whewell’s (1794–1866) ‘Discoverer’s Induction’, and argue that it 21 supplies a strikingly accurate characterization of the logic behind many statistical methods, exploratory 22 data analysis (EDA) in particular. Such methods are additionally well-suited as a point of evaluation of 23 Whewell’s philosophy since the central techniques of EDA were not invented until after Whewell’s death, 24 and so couldn’t have influenced his views. The fact that the quantitative details of some very general 25 methods (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How and Why I Write History of Science.Menachem Fisch - 2013 - Science in Context 26 (4):573-585.
    I have always been a philosopher at heart. I write history of science and history of its philosophy primarily as a philosopher wary of his abstractions and broad conceptualizations. But that has not always been the case. Lakatos famously portrayed history of science as the testing ground for theories of scientific rationality. But he did so along the crudest Hegelian lines that did injury both to Hegel and to the history and methodology of science. Since science is ultimately rational, he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Whewell’s tidal researches: scientific practice and philosophical methodology.Steffen Ducheyne - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (1):26-40.
    Primarily between 1833 and 1840, William Whewell attempted to accomplish what natural philosophers and scientists since at least Galileo had failed to do: to provide a systematic and broad-ranged study of the tides and to attempt to establish a general scientific theory of tidal phenomena. I document the close interaction between Whewell’s philosophy of science and his scientific practice as a tidologist. I claim that the intertwinement between Whewell’s methodology and his tidology is more fundamental than has hitherto been documented.Keywords: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation