Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Defining Deduction.Mark Vorobej - 1992 - Informal Logic 14 (2).
    This paper defends the view that the classification of an argument as being deductive ought to rest exclusively upon psychological considerations; specifically, upon whether the argument's author holds certain beliefs. This account is justified on theoretical and pedagogical grounds, and situated within a general taxonomy of competing proposals. Epistemological difficulties involved in the application of psychological definitions are recognized but claimed to be ineliminable from the praetice of argumentation. The paper concludes by discussing embryonic arguments where the author's relevant beliefs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Applying Soundness Standards to Qualified Reasoning.Robert H. Ennis - 2004 - Informal Logic 24 (1):23-39.
    Defining qualified reasoning as reasoning containing such loose qualifying words as 'probably,' 'usually,' 'probable, 'likely,' 'ceteris paribus,' and 'primafacie, Ennis argues that typical cases of qualified reasoning, though they might be good arguments, are deductively invalid, implying that such arguments fail soundness standards. He considers and rejects several possible alternative ways of viewing such cases, ending with a proposal for applying qualified soundness standards, which requires employment of sufficient background knowledge, sensitivity, experience and understanding of the situation. All of this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Rational Comprehension of Arguments in Theoretical Texts: A Program for an Argumentative-Linguistic Approach. [REVIEW]Lev G. Vassiliev - 2003 - Argumentation 17 (1):21-34.
    A method of linguistically-oriented reasoning comprehension is proposed. It is based on semiological principles of text comprehension. Both content and form are essential for comprehending argumentative texts. A text recipient is viewed as a rational judge trying to detect all the components of the argument he/she considers and thus to see if the argument is consistent. Elementary and higher level argumentative units of the text are discovered by applying a modified S. Toulmin's model of argumentative functions. Validity and correctness of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Informal Logic Bibliography.Hans V. Hansen - 1990 - Informal Logic 12 (3).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Reasonable Doubt: A Note on Neutral Illatives and Arguments.G. C. Goddu - 1999 - Argumentation 13 (3):243-250.
    George Bowles and Thomas Gilbert claim that illatives such as so, therefore, and hence convey the meaning that the premise confers upon the conclusion a probability greater than 1/2. This claim is false, for there are straightforward uses of these illatives that do not convey the meaning that the probability is greater than 1/2. In addition, because Bowles' and Gilbert's claim is false, a revision of their definition of argument is required.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Freeman on Deduction/Induction.George Englebretsen - 1984 - Informal Logic 6 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The probabilistic import of illatives.George Bowles & Thomas E. Gilbert - 1993 - Argumentation 7 (3):247-262.
    It is not only overtly probabilistic illatives like ‘makes it certain that’ but also apparently non-probabilistic ones like ‘therefore’ that have probabilistic import. Illatives like ‘therefore’ convey the meaning that the premise confers on the conclusion a probability not only greater than 0 but also greater than 1/2. But because they do not say whether that probability is equal to or less than 1, these illatives are appropriately called ‘neutral’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Deductive/Inductive Distinction.George Bowles - 1994 - Informal Logic 16 (3):159-184.
    In this paper I examine five distinctions between deductive and inductive arguments, concluding that the best of the five defines a deductive argument as one in which conclusive favorable relevance to its conclusion is attributed to its premises, and an inductive argument as any argument that is not deductive. This distinction, unlike its rivals, is both exclusive and exhaustive; permits both good and bad arguments of each kind; and is both useful and needed in evaluating at least some arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Evaluating Arguments: The Premise-Conclusion Relation.George Bowles - 1991 - Informal Logic 13 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations