Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. How embodied is time?Rakesh Sengupta - 2018 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 35 (3):431-445.
    It is a standard understanding that we live in time. In fact, the whole physical world as described in sciences is based on the idea of objective time. For centuries, we have defined time ever so minutely, basing them on finer and finer event measurements that we do not even notice that we have made an inductive leap when it comes to time—we can measure time, so we experience time. In the current work, I wish to critique this inductive leap (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a Model of Functional Brain Processes I: Central Nervous System Functional Micro-architecture.Mark H. Bickhard - 2015 - Axiomathes 25 (3):217-238.
    Standard semantic information processing models—information in; information processed; information out —lend themselves to standard models of the functioning of the brain in terms, e.g., of threshold-switch neurons connected via classical synapses. That is, in terms of sophisticated descendants of McCulloch and Pitts models. I argue that both the cognition and the brain sides of this framework are incorrect: cognition and thought are not constituted as forms of semantic information processing, and the brain does not function in terms of passive input (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Deleuze and Geophilosophy: A Guide and Glossary.Mark Bonta & John Protevi - 2019 - Edinburgh University Press.
    This is the first book to use complexity theory to open up the 'geophilosophy' developed by Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari in A Thousand Plateaus, Anti-Oedipus and What is Philosophy?.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Empirical data base for simulation: Firing rates and axonal conduction velocity for cortical neurones.Robert Miller - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):304-305.
    Simulation of brain dynamics requires the use of accurate empirical data. This commentary points out major errors in some of the empirical data used in Wright & Laley's simulation. The simulation is quantitatively very different from the real cortex, and may also have important qualitative differences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there chaos in the brain?Hubert Preissl, Werner Lutzenberger & Friedemann Pulvermüller - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):307-308.
    For some years there has been a controversy about whether brain state variables such as EEG or neuronal spike trains exhibit chaotic behaviour. Wright & Liley claim that the local dynamics measured by spike trains or local field potentials exhibit chaotic behaviour, but global measures like EEG should be governed by linear dynamics. We propose a different scheme. Based on simulation studies and various experiments, we suggest that the pointwise dimension of EEG time series may provide some valuable information about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why does the human brain need to be a nonlinear system?Zbigniew J. Kowalik, Andrzej Wrobel & Andrzej Rydz - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):302-303.
    We focus on one aspect of Wright & Liley's target article: the linearity of the EEG. According to the authors, some nonlinear models of the cortex can be reduced (approximated) to the linear case at the millimetric scale. We argue here that the statement about the linear character of EEG is too strong and that EEG exhibits nonlinear features which cannot be ignored.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How representation works is more important than what representations are.Shimon Edelman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):630-631.
    A theory of representation is incomplete if it states “representations areX” whereXcan be symbols, cell assemblies, functional states, or the flock of birds fromTheaetetus, without explaining the nature of the link between the universe ofXs and the world. Amit's thesis, equating representations with reverberations in Hebbian cell assemblies, will only be considered a solution to the problem of representation when it is complemented by a theory of how a reverberation in the brain can be a representation of anything.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematics of Hebbian attractors.Morris W. Hirsch - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):633-634.
    The concept of an attractor in a mathematical dynamical system is reviewed. Emphasis is placed on the distinction between a cell assembly, the corresponding attractor, and the attractor dynamics. The biological significance of these entities is discussed, especially the question of whether the representation of the stimulus requires the full attractor dynamics, or merely the cell assembly as a set of reverberating neurons. Comparison is made to Freeman's study of dynamic patterns in olfaction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Local or transcortical assemblies? Some evidence from cognitive neuroscience.Friedemann Pulvermüller & Hubert Preissl - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):640-641.
    Amit defines cell assemblies aslocal cortical neuron populationswith strong internal connections. However, Hebb himself proposed that cell assemblies are distributed over different cortical areas (nonlocal ortranscortical assemblies). We review evidence from cognitive neuroscience and neuropsychology supporting the assumption that cell assemblies are transcortical.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Music and dance as a coalition signaling system.Edward H. Hagen & Gregory A. Bryant - 2003 - Human Nature 14 (1):21-51.
    Evidence suggests that humans might have neurological specializations for music processing, but a compelling adaptationist account of music and dance is lacking. The sexual selection hypothesis cannot easily account for the widespread performance of music and dance in groups (especially synchronized performances), and the social bonding hypothesis has severe theoretical difficulties. Humans are unique among the primates in their ability to form cooperative alliances between groups in the absence of consanguineal ties. We propose that this unique form of social organization (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Music, neuroscience, and the psychology of wellbeing: A précis.Adam M. Croom - 2012 - Frontiers in Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 2 (393):393.
    In Flourish, the positive psychologist Martin Seligman (2011) identifies five commonly recognized factors that are characteristic of human flourishing or wellbeing: (1) “positive emotion,” (2) “relationships,” (3) “engagement,” (4) “achievement,” and (5) “meaning” (p. 24). Although there is no settled set of necessary and sufficient conditions neatly circumscribing the bounds of human flourishing (Seligman, 2011), we would mostly likely consider a person that possessed high levels of these five factors as paradigmatic or prototypical of human flourishing. Accordingly, if we wanted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Cybernetic legal analysis and human agency.Alessandra Lippucci - 1998 - Res Publica 4 (1):77-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Heideggerian ai failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 2007 - Philosophical Psychology 20 (2):247 – 268.
    MICHAEL WHEELER Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005432 pages, ISBN: 0262232405 (hbk); $35.001.When I was teaching at MIT in the 1960s, students from the Artificial Intelligence Laboratory would come to...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Ruthless reductionism: A review essay of John Bickle's philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. [REVIEW]Huib L. de Jong & Maurice K. D. Schouten - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (4):473-486.
    John Bickle's new book on philosophy and neuroscience is aptly subtitled 'a ruthlessly reductive account'. His 'new wave metascience' is a massive attack on the relative autonomy that psychology enjoyed until recently, and goes even beyond his previous (Bickle, J. (1998). Psychoneural reduction: The new wave. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.) new wave reductionsism. Reduction of functional psychology to (cognitive) neuroscience is no longer ruthless enough; we should now look rather to cellular or molecular neuroscience at the lowest possible level for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The puzzle of attention, the importance of metaphors.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (3):331-351.
    I have two goals in this paper. First, I want to show by example that inferences about theoretical entities are relatively contingent affairs. Previously accepted conceptual metaphors in science set both the general form of new theories and our acceptance of the theories as plausible. In addition, they determine how we define the relevant parameters in investigating phenomena in the first place. These items then determine how we conceptualize things in the world. Second, and maybe more importantly, I want to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is the distribution of coherence a test of the model?Theodore H. Bullock - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):296-296.
    Does the Wright & Liley model predict: (1) that subdural and hippocampal EEGs coherence tend to rise and fall in parallel for many frequencies, (2) that it is locally high or low within 10mm and falls steeply on average or, (3) that it is in constant flux, mostly rising and falling within 5–15 sec?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reverberations of Hebbian thinking.Josef P. Rauschecker - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):642-643.
    Cortical reverberations may induce synaptic changes that underlie developmental plasticity as well as long-term memory. They may be especially important for the consolidation of synaptic changes. Reverberations in cortical networks should have particular significance during development, when large numbers of new representations are formed. This includes the formation of representations across different sensory modalities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Where the adventure is.Elie Bienenstock & Stuart Geman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):627-628.
    Interpreting the Miyashita et al. experiments in terms of a cellassembly representation does not adequately explain the performance of Miyashita's monkeys on novel stimuli. We will argue that the latter observations point to acompositionalrepresentation and suggest a dynamics involving rapid and reversible binding of distinct activity patterns.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What do double dissociations prove?Guy C. Orden, Bruce F. Pennington & Gregory O. Stone - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (1):111-172.
    Brain damage may doubly dissociate cognitive modules, but the practice of revealing dissociations is predicated on modularity being true (T. Shallice, 1988). This article questions the utility of assuming modularity, as it examines a paradigmatic double dissociation of reading modules. Reading modules illustrate two general problems. First, modularity fails to converge on a fixed set of exclusionary criteria that define pure cases. As a consequence, competing modular theories force perennial quests for purer cases, which simply perpetuates growth in the list (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Worldview transformation and the development of social consciousness.Marilyn Mandala Schlitz, Cassandra Vieten & Elizabeth M. Miller - 2010 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 17 (7-8):7-8.
    In this paper, we examine how increasing understanding and explicit awareness of social consciousness can develop through transformations in worldview. Based on a model that emerged from a series of qualitative and quantitative studies on worldview transformation, we identify five developmental levels of social consciousness: embedded, self-reflexive, engaged, collaborative, and resonant. As a person's worldview transforms, awareness can expand to include each of these levels, leading to enhanced prosocial experiences and behaviours. Increased social consciousness can in turn stimulate further transformations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Consciousness.John R. Searle - 2000 - Intellectica 31:85-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Time, change, and sociocultural communication.Thomas J. Bruneau - 2007 - Sign Systems Studies 35 (1-2):89-116.
    The temporal orientations of any sociocultural grouping are major factors comprising its central identity. The manner in which the past (memories), the present (perception), and the future (anticipation/expectation) are commonly articulated also concern cultural identity. The identity of a cultural group is altered by developmental changes in time keeping and related objective, scientific temporalities.Three modes of temporality, objective, narrative, and transcendental, congruent with different kinds of brain processes, are common throughout our planet. Objective temporality tends to alter and replace traditional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rhythmicity in the EEG and global stabilization of the average level of excitation in the cerebral cortex.M. N. Zhadin - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):309-310.
    The network model of EEG formation has revealed a unified mechanism for disparate EEG phenomena: for various reactions as well as for ontogenetic and phylogenetic differences. EEG rhythmicity was shown to be an external manifestation of the functioning of the intracortical stabilizing system which provides normal informational operations in the cerebral cortex.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Multiscale modeling of brain dynamics depends upon approximations at each scale.J. J. Wright & D. T. J. Liley - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):310-320.
    We outline fresh findings that show that our macroscopic electrocorticographic (ECoG) simulations can account for synchronous multiunit pulse oscillations at separate, simultaneously activated cortical sites and the associated gamma-band ECoG activity. We clarify our views on the approximations of dynamic class applicable to neural events at macroscopic and microscopic scales, and the analogies drawn to classes of ANN behaviour. We accept the need to introduce memory processes and detailed anatomical and physiological information into any future developments of our simulations. On (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How do local reverberations achieve global integration?J. J. Wright - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):644-645.
    Amit's Hebbian model risks being overexplanatory, since it does not depend on specific physiological modelling of cortical ANNs, but concentrates on those phenomena which are modelled by a large class of ANNs. While offering a strong demonstration of the presence of Hebb's “cell assemblies,” it does not offer an equal account of Hebb's “phase sequence” concept.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamics of the brain at global and microscopic scales: Neural networks and the EEG.J. J. Wright & D. T. J. Liley - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):285-295.
    There is some complementarity of models for the origin of the electroencephalogram (EEG) and neural network models for information storage in brainlike systems. From the EEG models of Freeman, of Nunez, and of the authors' group we argue that the wavelike processes revealed in the EEG exhibit linear and near-equilibrium dynamics at macroscopic scale, despite extremely nonlinear – probably chaotic – dynamics at microscopic scale. Simulations of cortical neuronal interactions at global and microscopic scales are then presented. The simulations depend (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Rhythms of Discontnet: Synchrony Impedes Performance and Group Functioning in an Interdependent Coordination Task.Connor Wood, Catherine Caldwell-Harris & Anna Stopa - 2018 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 18 (1-2):154-179.
    Synchrony — intentional, rhythmic motor entrainment in groups — is an important topic in social psychology and the cognitive science of religion. Synchrony has been found to increase trust and prosociality, to index interpersonal attention, and to induce perceptions of similarity and group cohesion. Causal explanations suggest that synchrony induces neurocognitive self-other blurring, leading participants to process one another as identical. In light of such findings, researchers have highlighted synchrony as an important evolved tool for establishing and maintaining collective identity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Facial expression of pain: An evolutionary account.Amanda C. De C. Williams - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (4):439-455.
    This paper proposes that human expression of pain in the presence or absence of caregivers, and the detection of pain by observers, arises from evolved propensities. The function of pain is to demand attention and prioritise escape, recovery, and healing; where others can help achieve these goals, effective communication of pain is required. Evidence is reviewed of a distinct and specific facial expression of pain from infancy to old age, consistent across stimuli, and recognizable as pain by observers. Voluntary control (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The form of chaos in the noisy brain can manifest function.Ichiro Tsuda - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):309-309.
    I would like to emphasize the significance of chaotic dynamics at both local and macroscopic levels in the cortex. The basic notions dealt with in this commentary will be noise-induced order, chaotic “itinerancy” and dissipative structure. Wright & Laley's theory would be partially misleading, since emergent nonlinearity rather than the linearity at even a macroscopic level can actually subserve cortical functions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the time ripe for integration of scales?Daniel J. Amit - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):295-296.
    Some concepts relating to learned, structured functioning of local modules in neocortex are clarified in order to ensure that the integration from the small scale to the global attempted by Wright & Liley does not miss the target.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Multiscale modeling of the brain should be validated in more detail against the biological data.Harry R. Erwin - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):297-298.
    Wright & Liley provide an advance in addressing the interaction of multiple scales of processing in the brain. It should address in more detail the biological evidence that underlies the models it proposes to replace.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comparative reduction of theories — or over-simplification?Edgar Koerner - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):301-302.
    To model the organization of levels' of cortical dynamics, at least some general scheme for hierarchy, functional diversity, and proper intrinsic control must be provided. Rhythmic control forces the system to iterate its state by short trajectories, which makes it much more stable and predictable without discarding the desirable ability of chaotic systems to make rapid phase transitions. Rhythmic control provides a fundamentally different systems dynamics, one not provided by models that allow the emergence of continuous trajectories in the systems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Association and computation with cell assemblies.Frank der van Velde - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):643-644.
    The cell assembly is an important concept for cognitive psychology. Cognitive processing will to a large extent depend on the relations that can exist between different assemblies. A potential relation between assemblies can already be seen in the occurrence of (classical) conditioning. However, the resulting associations between assemblies only produce behavioristic processing or so-called regular computation. Higher-level cognitive abilities most likely result from nonregular computation. I discuss the possibility of this form of computation in terms of cell assemblies.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reverberation reconsidered: On the path to cognitive theory.Eric Chown - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):628-629.
    Amit's work addresses a critical issue in cognitive science: the structure of neural representations. The use of Hebbian cell assemblies is a positive step, and we now need to consider its role in a larger cognitive theory. When considering the dynamics of a system built out of attractors, a more limited version of reverberation becomes necessary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Synchronicity, Mind, and Matter.Wlodzislaw Duch - 2002 - International Journal of Transpersonal Studies 21:153-168.
    Experiments with remote perception and Random Event Generators (REG) performed over the last decades show small but significant anomalous effects. Since these effects seem to be independent of spatial and temporal distance, they appear to be in disagreement with the standard scientific worldview. A very simple explanation of quantum mechanics is pre- sented, rejecting all unjustified claims about the world. A view of mind in agreement with cognitive neuroscience is introduced. It is argued that mind and consciousness are emer- gent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • In the Light of the Environment: Evolution Through Biogrammars Not Programmers.Ken Richardson - 2020 - Biological Theory 15 (4):212-222.
    Biological understanding of human cognitive functions is incomplete because of failure to understand the evolution of complex functions and organisms in general. Here, that failure is attributed to an aspect of the standard neo-Darwinian synthesis, namely commitment to evolution by natural selection of genetic programs in stable environments, a position that cannot easily explain the evolution of complexity. When we turn to consider more realistic, highly changeable environments, however, another possibility becomes clearer. An alternative to genetic programs—dubbed “biogrammars”—is proposed here (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Levels, models, and brain activities: Neurodynamics is pluralistic.Péter Érdi - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):296-297.
    Some dichotomies related to modeling electrocortical activities are analyzed. Attractor neural networks versus biologically motivated models, near-equilibrium versus nonequilibrium processes, linear and nonlinear dynamics, stochastic and chaotic patterns, local and global scale simulation of cortical activities are discussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How to decide whether a neural representation is a cognitive concept?Maartje E. J. Raijmakers & Peter C. M. Molenaar - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):641-642.
    A distinction should be made between the formation of stimulus-driven associations and cognitive concepts. To test the learning mode of a neural network, we propose a simple and classic input-output test: the discrimination shift task. Feed-forward PDP models appear to form stimulus-driven associations. A Hopfield network should be extended to apply the test.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The EEG data indicate stochastic nonlinearity.Walter S. Pritchard - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):308-308.
    Wright & Liley contrast their theory that the global dynamics of the EEG are linear with that of Freeman, who hypothesizes an EEG governed by (nonlinear) deterministic-chaotic dynamics. A “call for further discussion” on the part of the authors is made as to how either theory fits with experimental findings indicating that EEG dynamics are non-linear but stochastic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The problems of cognitive dynamical models.Jean Petitot - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):640-640.
    Amit's “Attractor Neural Network” perspective on cognition raises difficult technical problems already met by prior dynamical models. This commentary sketches briefly some of them concerning the internal topological structure of attractors, the constituency problem, the possibility of activating simultaneously several attractors, and the different kinds of dynamical structures one can use to model brain activity: point attractors, strange attractors, synchronized arrays of oscillators, synfire chains, and so forth.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamics of the brain — from the statistical properties of neural signals to the development of representations.Andrew Oliver - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):306-307.
    The unification of microscopic and macroscopic models of brain behaviour is of paramount importance and Wright & Liley's target article provides some important groundwork. In this commentary, I propose that a useful approach for the future is to incorporate a developmental perspective into such models. This may be an important constraint, providing a key to understanding the nature of macroscopic measures of brain function such as functional measures like ERP.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Agency and the theory of quantum vacuum interaction.Raymond Trevor Bradley - 2000 - World Futures 55 (3):227-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The evolution of consciousness as a self-organizing information system in the society of other such systems.Allan Combs & Sally Goerner - 1997 - World Futures 50 (1):609-616.
    (1997). The evolution of consciousness as a self‐organizing information system in the society of other such systems. World Futures: Vol. 50, No. 1-4, pp. 609-616.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Multiscale neocortical dynamics, experimental EEG measures, and global facilitation of local cell assemblies.Paul L. Nunez - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):305-306.
    Multiscale dynamics, linear approximations, global boundary conditions, experimental verification, and global influences on local cell assemblies are considered in the context of Wright & Liley's work. W&L provide a nice introduction to these issues and a reasonable simulation of intermediate scale dynamics, but the model does not adequately simulate combined local and global processes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Another ANN model for the Miyashita experiments.Masahiko Morita - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):639-640.
    The Miyashita experiments are very interesting and the results should be examined from a viewpoint of attractor dynamics. Amit's target article shows a path toward realistic modeling by artificial neural networks (ANN), but it is not necessarily the only one. I introduce another model that can explain a substantial part of the empirical observations and makes an interesting prediction. This model consists of such units that have nonmonotonic input-output characteristics with local inhibition neurons.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chaos in induced rhythms of the brain – the value of ERP studies.Márk Molnár - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):305-305.
    Event-related potentials (ERPs) – neglected almost entirely by Wright & Liley – allow objective investigation of information processing in the brain. The application of chaos theory to such an analysis broadens this possibility. Through the use of the point correlation dimension (PD2) accurate dimensional analysis of different Event-Related Potential components such as the P3 wave is possible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attractors – don't get sucked in.Peter M. Milner - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):638-639.
    Every immediate memory is unique; it is therefore unlikely to consist of an attractor or even a combination of attractors. In the present state of knowledge about the chemistry of synaptic transmission, there is no reason to look beyond neurons that directly receive sensory afferents for the afterdischarges that correspond to active memories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Energy, information, detection, and action.Claire F. Michaels & Raoul R. D. Oudejans - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (2):230-230.
    Before one can talk about global arrays and multimodal detection, one must be clear about the concept of information: How is it different from energy and how is it detected? And can it come to specify a needed movement? We consider these issues in our commentary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ruthless reductionism: A review essay of John Bickle's Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account.Huib Looren de Jong & Maurice K. D. Schouten - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (4):473-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Eating soup with chopsticks: Dogmas, difficulties and alternatives in the study of conscious experience.Rafael E. Núñez - 1997 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 (2):143-166.
    The recently celebrated division into ‘easy’ and ‘hard’ problems of consciousness is unfortunate and misleading. Built on functionalist grounds, it carves up the subject matter by declaring that the most elusive parts need a fundamentally and intrinsically different solution. What we have, rather, are ‘difficult’ problems of conscious experience, but problems that are not difficult per se. Their difficulty is relative, among other things, to the kind of solution one is looking for and the tools used to accomplish the task. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations