Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On notions of computability-theoretic reduction between Π21 principles.Denis R. Hirschfeldt & Carl G. Jockusch - 2016 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 16 (1):1650002.
    Several notions of computability-theoretic reducibility between [Formula: see text] principles have been studied. This paper contributes to the program of analyzing the behavior of versions of Ramsey’s Theorem and related principles under these notions. Among other results, we show that for each [Formula: see text], there is an instance of RT[Formula: see text] all of whose solutions have PA degree over [Formula: see text] and use this to show that König’s Lemma lies strictly between RT[Formula: see text] and RT[Formula: see (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the Strength of Ramsey's Theorem.David Seetapun & Theodore A. Slaman - 1995 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 36 (4):570-582.
    We show that, for every partition F of the pairs of natural numbers and for every set C, if C is not recursive in F then there is an infinite set H, such that H is homogeneous for F and C is not recursive in H. We conclude that the formal statement of Ramsey's Theorem for Pairs is not strong enough to prove , the comprehension scheme for arithmetical formulas, within the base theory , the comprehension scheme for recursive formulas. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Htp-complete rings of rational numbers.Russell Miller - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (1):252-272.
    For a ring R, Hilbert’s Tenth Problem $HTP$ is the set of polynomial equations over R, in several variables, with solutions in R. We view $HTP$ as an enumeration operator, mapping each set W of prime numbers to $HTP$, which is naturally viewed as a set of polynomials in $\mathbb {Z}[X_1,X_2,\ldots ]$. It is known that for almost all W, the jump $W'$ does not $1$ -reduce to $HTP$. In contrast, we show that every Turing degree contains a set W (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The complexity of orbits of computably enumerable sets.Peter A. Cholak, Rodney Downey & Leo A. Harrington - 2008 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):69 - 87.
    The goal of this paper is to announce there is a single orbit of the c.e. sets with inclusion, ε, such that the question of membership in this orbit is ${\Sigma _1^1 }$ -complete. This result and proof have a number of nice corollaries: the Scott rank of ε is $\omega _1^{{\rm{CK}}}$ + 1; not all orbits are elementarily definable; there is no arithmetic description of all orbits of ε; for all finite α ≥ 9, there is a properly $\Delta (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Superhighness.Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen & Andrée Nies - 2009 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 50 (4):445-452.
    We prove that superhigh sets can be jump traceable, answering a question of Cole and Simpson. On the other hand, we show that such sets cannot be weakly 2-random. We also study the class $superhigh^\diamond$ and show that it contains some, but not all, of the noncomputable K-trivial sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • 1995 European Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.Johann A. Makowsky - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):73-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A non-inversion theorem for the jump operator.Richard A. Shore - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 40 (3):277-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • A degree-theoretic definition of the ramified analytical hierarchy.Carl G. Jockusch & Stephen G. Simpson - 1976 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 10 (1):1-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Limits on jump inversion for strong reducibilities.Barbara F. Csima, Rod Downey & Keng Meng Ng - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (4):1287-1296.
    We show that Sacks' and Shoenfield's analogs of jump inversion fail for both tt- and wtt-reducibilities in a strong way. In particular we show that there is a ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{2}^{0}$ set B > tt ∅′ such that there is no c.e. set A with A′ ≡ wtt B. We also show that there is a ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{2}^{0}$ set C > tt ∅′ such that there is no ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{2}^{0}$ set D with D′ ≡ wtt C.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Reducibility Related To Being Hyperimmune-free.Frank Stephan & Liang Yu - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (7-8):1291-1300.
    The main topic of the present work is the relation that a set X is strongly hyperimmune-free relative to Y . Here X is strongly hyperimmune-free relative to Y if and only if for every partial X -recursive function p there is a partial Y -recursive function q such that every a in the domain of p is also in the domain of q and satisfies p (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • About Segment Complexity of Turing Reductions.Valeriy K. Bulitko - 1999 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 45 (4):561-571.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Arithmetical Reducibilities I.Alan L. Selman - 1971 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 17 (1):335-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Reducibility orderings: Theories, definability and automorphisms.Anil Nerode & Richard A. Shore - 1980 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 18 (1):61-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Completely mitotic c.e. degrees and non-jump inversion.Evan J. Griffiths - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 132 (2-3):181-207.
    A completely mitotic computably enumerable degree is a c.e. degree in which every c.e. set is mitotic, or equivalently in which every c.e. set is autoreducible. There are known to be low, low2, and high completely mitotic degrees, though the degrees containing non-mitotic sets are dense in the c.e. degrees. We show that there exists an upper cone of c.e. degrees each of which contains a non-mitotic set, and that the completely mitotic c.e. degrees are nowhere dense in the c.e. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark