Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Authorship of thoughts in thought insertion: What is it for a thought to be one's own?Max Seeger - 2015 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (6):837-855.
    In thought insertion, subjects experience thoughts which they claim not to be their own. What they claim, it is typically said, is that the thought is not theirs in the sense that they are not the agent or author of the thought. But what does it mean to be the agent or author of a thought? The most intuitive idea is that for a thought to be one's own means for the thought to causally originate within the subject. I defend (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The generative-rules definition of creativity.Joseph O'Rourke - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):547-547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Making Sense of an Endorsement Model of Thought‐Insertion.Michael Sollberger - 2014 - Mind and Language 29 (5):590-612.
    Experiences of thought-insertion are a first-rank, diagnostically central symptom of schizophrenia. Schizophrenic patients who undergo such delusional mental states report being first-personally aware of an occurrent conscious thought which is not theirs, but which belongs to an external cognitive agent. Patients seem to be right about what they are thinking but mistaken about who is doing the thinking. It is notoriously difficult to make sense of such delusions. One general approach to explaining the etiology of monothematic delusions has come to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Creativity: Myths? Mechanisms.Michel Treisman - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):554-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creativity, madness, and extra strong Al.K. W. M. Fulford - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):542-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious thought processes and creativity.Maria F. Ippolito - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):546-547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Précis of The creative mind: Myths and mechanisms.Margaret A. Boden - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):519-531.
    What is creativity? One new idea may be creative, whereas another is merely new: What's the difference? And how is creativity possible? These questions about human creativity can be answered, at least in outline, using computational concepts. There are two broad types of creativity, improbabilist and impossibilist. Improbabilist creativity involves novel combinations of familiar ideas. A deeper type involves METCS: the mapping, exploration, and transformation of conceptual spaces. It is impossibilist, in that ideas may be generated which – with respect (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Values‐based practice: Fulford's dangerous idea.Kenneth W. M. Fulford - 2013 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 19 (3):537-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Examining fallacies in diagnostic reasoning.C. W. Staden - 2013 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 19 (3):528-530.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The value of evidence and evidence of values: bringing together values‐based and evidence‐based practice in policy and service development in mental health.Kenneth W. M. Fulford - 2011 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5):976-987.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Radical liberal values‐based practice.Tim Thornton - 2011 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5):988-991.
    Values based practice is a radical view of the place of values in medicine which develops from a philosophical analysis of values, illness and the role of ethical principles. It denies two attractive and traditional views of medicine: that diagnosis is a merely factual matter and that the values that should guide treatment and management can be codified in principles. But it goes further in the adoption of a radical liberal view: that right or good outcome should be replaced by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Bringing together values‐based and evidence‐based medicine: UK Department of Health Initiatives in the 'Personalization' of Care.K. W. M. Bill Fulford - 2011 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (2):341-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Critical thinking vs. moral expertise: a commentary on 'The rationale of value‐laden medicine' (Kottow 2002; Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 8, 77–84). [REVIEW]Michael Loughlin - 2003 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 9 (1):92-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Towards an evidence‐based 'Medicine of the Person': the contribution of psychiatry to health care provision.John L. Cox - 2008 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5):694-698.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ill Health or Illness: A Reply to Hofmann. [REVIEW]Lennart Nordenfelt - 2013 - Health Care Analysis 21 (4):298-305.
    In this article I respond to Björn Hofmann’s criticism of some elements in my theory of health. Hofmann’s main objective is to question “Nordenfelt’s basic premise that you can be ill without having negative first-person experiences, and to investigate the consequences of abandoning the premise.” One of Hofmann’s critical points is that my theory of health does not lend voice to the individual. My response is essentially conducted in four steps: (1) I question the aim of conceptual analysis that Hofmann (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Health and Morality: Two Conceptually Distinct Categories? [REVIEW]Per-Anders Tengland - 2012 - Health Care Analysis 20 (1):66-83.
    When seeing immoral actions, criminal or not, we sometimes deem the people who perform them unhealthy. This is especially so if the actions are of a serious nature, e.g. involving murder, assault, or rape. We turn our moral evaluation into an evaluation about health and illness. This tendency is partly supported by some diagnoses found in the DMS-IV, such as Antisocial personality disorder, and the ICD-10, such as Dissocial personality disorder. The aim of the paper is to answer the question: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Extending disorder: essentialism, family resemblance and secondary sense. [REVIEW]Neil Pickering - 2013 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 16 (2):185-195.
    It is commonly thought that mental disorder is a valid concept only in so far as it is an extension of or continuous with the concept of physical disorder. A valid extension has to meet two criteria: determination and coherence. Essentialists meet these criteria through necessary and sufficient conditions for being a disorder. Two Wittgensteinian alternatives to essentialism are considered and assessed against the two criteria. These are the family resemblance approach and the secondary sense approach. Where the focus is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Beyond Naturalism and Normativism: Reconceiving the 'Disease' Debate.Jeremy Simon - 2007 - Philosophical Papers 36 (3):343-370.
    In considering the debate about the meaning of ‘disease’, the positions are generally presented as falling into two categories: naturalist, e.g., Boorse, and normativist, e.g., Engelhardt and many others. This division is too coarse, and obscures much of what is going on in this debate. I therefore propose that accounts of the meaning of ‘disease’ be assessed according to Hare’s (1997) taxonomy of evaluative terms. Such an analysis will allow us to better understand both individual positions and their inter-relationships. Most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Aristotelian Accounts of Disease—What are they good for?Rachel Cooper - 2007 - Philosophical Papers 36 (3):427-442.
    In this paper I will argue that Aristotelian accounts of disease cannot provide us with an adequate descriptive account of our concept of disease. In other words, they fail to classify conditions as either diseases, or non-diseases, in a way that is consistent with commonplace intuitions. This being said, Aristotelian accounts of disease are not worthless. Aristotelian approaches cannot offer a decent descriptive account of our concept of disease, but they do offer resources for improving on the ways in which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Making sense of stories: the use of patient narratives within mental health care research.Geir F. Lorem - 2008 - Nursing Philosophy 9 (1):62-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why the idea of framework propositions cannot contribute to an understanding of delusions.Tim Thornton - 2007 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (2):159-175.
    One of the tasks that recent philosophy of psychiatry has taken upon itself is to extend the range of understanding to some of those aspects of psychopathology that Jaspers deemed beyond its limits. Given the fundamental difficulties of offering a literal interpretation of the contents of primary delusions, a number of alternative strategies have been put forward including regarding them as abnormal versions of framework propositions described by Wittgenstein in On Certainty. But although framework propositions share some of the apparent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A two-dimensional theory of health.Per-Anders Tengland - 2007 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 28 (4):257-284.
    The starting point for the contemporary debate about theories of health should be the holistic theory of Lennart Nordenfelt, claims George Khushf, not the refuted theory of Christopher Boorse. The present paper is an attempt to challenge Nordenfelt and to present an alternative theory to his and other theories, including Boorse’s. The main problems with Nordenfelt’s theory are that it is relativistic, that it leads to counter-intuitive results as to what goals can count as healthy, that it focuses on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The birth of an idea.Liane M. Gabora - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):543-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creative thinking presupposes the capacity for thought.James H. Fetzer - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):539-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creativity theory: Detail and testability.K. J. Gilhooly - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):544-545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Camouflage is still no defence – another plea for a straight answer to the question 'what is bioethics?'.Michael Loughlin - 2004 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 10 (1):75-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Bioethical blind spots: Four flaws in the field of view of traditional bioethics. [REVIEW]K. W. M. Fulford - 1993 - Health Care Analysis 1 (2):155-162.
    In this paper it is argued that bioethics has tended to emphasise: ‘high tech’ areas of medicine at the expense of ‘low tech’ areas such as psychiatry; problems arising in treatment at the expense of those associated with diagnosis; questions of fact at the expense of questions of value; and applied ethics at the expense of philosophical theory. The common factor linking these four ‘bioethical blind spots’ is a failute to recognise the full extent to which medicine is an ethical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • When psychiatric diagnosis becomes an overworked tool.George Szmukler - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (8):517-520.
    A psychiatric diagnosis today is asked to serve many functions—clinical, research, medicolegal, delimiting insurance coverage, service planning, defining eligibility for state benefits , as well as providing rallying points for pressure groups and charities. These contexts require different notions of diagnosis to tackle the particular problem such a designation is meant to solve. In a number of instances, a ‘status’ definition is employed to tackle what is more appropriately seen as requiring a ‘functional’ approach . In these instances, a diagnosis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Health, Well-being and Beauty in Medicine.M. Musalek - 2013 - Topoi 32 (2):171-177.
    This paper aims at explicating the role of the connections and interactions between health, well being and beauty. The primary goal of all medical approaches, including the classic biomedical and humanistic or humane approaches, is to restore or create health, whereby medical approaches that include prevention go beyond the mere restoration of health to include the preservation of health. Equating well-being and thus health with a largely self-determined and joyful life, then not only does a healthy life become a beautiful (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Medico-ethical versus biological evaluationism, and the concept of disease.Jon A. Lindstrøm - 2012 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 15 (2):165-173.
    According to the ‘fact-plus-value’ model of pathology propounded by K. W. M. Fulford, ‘disease’ is a value term that ought to reflect a ‘balance of values’ stemming from patients and doctors and other ‘stakeholders’ in medical nosology. In the present article I take issue with his linguistic-analytical arguments for why pathological status must be relative to such a kind of medico-ethical normativity. Fulford is right to point out that Boorse and other naturalists are compelled to utilize evaluative terminology when they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Diagnosis, Power and Certainty: Response to Davis. [REVIEW]Malcolm Parker - 2010 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 7 (3):291-297.
    Lennard Davis’s Biocultural Critique of the alleged certainty of diagnosis (Davis Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 7:227−235, 2010) makes errors of fact concerning psychiatric diagnostic categories, misunderstands the role of power in the therapeutic relationship, and provides an unsubstantiated and vague alternative to the management of psychological distress via a conceptually outdated model of the relationships between physical and psychological disease and illness. This response demonstrates that diagnostic knowledge vouchsafes legitimate power to physicians, and via them relief to patients who suffer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Simplified models of the relationship between health and disease.Bjørn Hofmann - 2005 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 26 (5):355-377.
    The concepts of health and disease are crucial in defining the aim and the limits of modern medicine. Accordingly it is important to understand them and their relationship. However, there appears to be a discrepancy between scholars in philosophy of medicine and health care professionals with regard to these concepts. This article investigates health care professionals’ concepts of health and disease and the relationship between them. In order to do so, four different models are described and analyzed: the ideal model, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Creativity: A framework for research.Margaret A. Boden - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):558-570.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Imagery and creativity.Klaus Rehkämper - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):550-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the interface between science, medicine, faith and values in the individualization of clinical practice: a review and analysis of 'Medicine of the Person' Cox, J., Campbell, A. V. & Fulford, K. W. M., eds (2007). [REVIEW]Andrew Miles - 2009 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (6):1000-1024.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mental Illness, Metaphysics, Facts and Values.Chris Megone - 2007 - Philosophical Papers 36 (3):399-426.
    A number of prominent writers on the concept of mental illness/disease are committed to accounts which involve rejecting certain plausible widely held beliefs, namely: that it is part of the meaning of illness that it is bad for its possessor, so the concept of illness is essentially evaluative; that if a person has a mental illness, that is a fact about him; and that the same concept of illness is applicable in the case of mental illness as in that of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The production of the psychiatric subject: power, knowledge and Michel Foucault.Marc Roberts - 2005 - Nursing Philosophy 6 (1):33-42.
    The issue of power has become increasingly important within psychiatry, psychotherapy and mental health nursing generally. This paper will suggest that the work of Michel Foucault, the French philosopher and historian, has much to contribute to the discussion about the nature, existence and exercise of power within contemporary mental health care. As well as examining his original and challenging account of power, Foucault's emphasis on the intimate relationship between power and knowledge will be explored within the context of psychiatry and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Obesity as a Socially Defined Disease: Philosophical Considerations and Implications for Policy and Care.Bjørn Hofmann - 2016 - Health Care Analysis 24 (1):86-100.
    Obesity has generated significant worries amongst health policy makers and has obtained increased attention in health care. Obesity is unanimously defined as a disease in the health care and health policy literature. However, there are pragmatic and not principled reasons for this. This warrants an analysis of obesity according to standard conceptions of disease in the literature of philosophy of medicine. According to theories and definitions of disease referring to internal processes, obesity is not a disease. Obesity undoubtedly can result (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Individual differences, developmental changes, and social context.Dean Keith Simonton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):552-553.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neuro-ethics or neuro-values? Delusion and religious experience as a case study in values-based medicine.Kwm Fulford - 2004 - Poiesis and Praxis 2 (4):297-313.
    Values-Based Medicine (VBM) is the theory and practice of clinical decision-making for situations in which legitimately different values are in play. VBM is thus to values what Evidence-Based Medicine (EBM) is to facts. The theoretical basis of VBM is a branch of analytic philosophy called philosophical value theory. As a set of practical tools, VBM has been developed to meet the challenges of value diversity as they arise particularly in psychiatry. These challenges are illustrated in this paper by a case (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why Sports Medicine is not Medicine.Steven D. Edwards & Mike McNamee - 2006 - Health Care Analysis 14 (2):103-109.
    Sports Medicine as an apparent sub-class of medicine has developed apace over the past 30 years. Its recent trajectory has been evidenced by the emergence of specialist international research journals, standard texts, annual conferences, academic appointments and postgraduate courses. Although this field of enquiry and practice lays claim to the title ‘sports medicine’ this paper queries the legitimacy of that claim. Depending upon how ‘sports medicine’ and ‘medicine’ are defined, a plausible-sounding case can be made to show that sports medicine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mad, sad or bad. Moral luck and Michael Stone.Anita R. Noguera - 2000 - Nursing Philosophy 1 (2):158-168.
    This paper discusses the philosophical doctrine of moral luck, as described by Bernard Williams in his book of the same name. It first describes Williams' account and then uses the case of Michael Stone, a convicted murderer with a long history of mental disorder, and mental health practitioners’ interventions in his case, to test and debate Williams’ views. It examines four major areas of these, including the classical notion of moral luck, retroactive judgement, agent regret and justifiable and unjustifiable decision‐making. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Downplay of Suffering in Nordenfelt’s Theory of Illness.Bjørn Hofmann - 2013 - Health Care Analysis 21 (4):283-297.
    In his influential theory of health Nordenfelt bases the concepts of health and illness on the notions of ability and disability. A premise for this is that ability and disability provide a more promising, adequate, and useful basis than well-being and suffering. Nordenfelt uses coma and manic episodes as paradigm cases to show that this is so. Do these paradigm cases (and thus the premise) hold? What consequences does it have for the theory of health and illness if it they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Creativity, combination, and cognition.Terry Dartnall - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):537-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does Amphetamine Enhance Your Health? On the Distinction between Health and “Health-like” Enhancements.Per-Anders Tengland - 2015 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 40 (5):484-510.
    It is an imperative within health care, medicine, and public health to restore, preserve, and enhance health. Therefore, it is important to determine what kinds of enhancement are increases in health and what kinds are not. Taking as its point of departure two conceptions of health, namely, “manifest health” and “fundamental health,” the paper discusses various means used to enhance ability and well-being, and if those means, such as wheelchairs, implants, medicines, stimulants, or narcotics, enhance health. The fact that some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Respecting the phenomenology of human creativity.Victor A. Shames & John F. Kihlstrom - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The creative mind versus the creative computer.Robert W. Weisberg - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):555-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy, freedom and the public good: a review and analysis of 'Public Health Ethics' Holland, S. (2007).Andrew Miles & Michael Loughlin - 2009 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (5):838-858.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Szasz and his interlocutors: Reconsidering Thomas Szasz's "myth of mental illness" thesis.Mark Cresswell - 2008 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 38 (1):23–44.
    It is a matter of some irony that psychiatry's most trenchant critic for over four decades is himself a psychiatrist. I refer to Thomas S. Szasz. Szasz's core thesis may be succinctly rendered: mental illness is a “myth”, a “metaphor” which serves only to obscure the social and ethical “problems in living” we face as human beings. This paper reconsiders the conceptual bases of Szasz's assault on psychiatry and assesses recent counter-arguments of his critical interlocutors. It presents a defence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Madness versus badness: The ethical tension between the recovery movement and forensic psychiatry. [REVIEW]Claire L. Pouncey & Jonathan M. Lukens - 2010 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 31 (1):93-105.
    The mental health recovery movement promotes patient self-determination and opposes coercive psychiatric treatment. While it has made great strides towards these ends, its rhetoric impairs its political efficacy. We illustrate how psychiatry can share recovery values and yet appear to violate them. In certain criminal proceedings, for example, forensic psychiatrists routinely argue that persons with mental illness who have committed crimes are not full moral agents. Such arguments align with the recovery movement’s aim of providing appropriate treatment and services for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations