Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. erG A.Brief Guide Resource-Sensitivity-A. - 2003 - In R. Oehrle & J. Kruijff (eds.), resource sensitivity, binding, and anaphora. kluwer.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language acquisition in the absence of experience.Stephen Crain - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):597-612.
    A fundamental goal of linguistic theory is to explain how natural languages are acquired. This paper describes some recent findings on how learners acquire syntactic knowledge for which there is little, if any, decisive evidence from the environment. The first section presents several general observations about language acquisition that linguistic theory has tried to explain and discusses the thesis that certain linguistic properties are innate because they appear universally and in the absence of corresponding experience. A third diagnostic for innateness, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Syntactic parameter hunting: Little scavengers might get lost.Jill de Villiers - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):616-617.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science.Nicholas Evans & Stephen C. Levinson - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (5):429-448.
    Talk of linguistic universals has given cognitive scientists the impression that languages are all built to a common pattern. In fact, there are vanishingly few universals of language in the direct sense that all languages exhibit them. Instead, diversity can be found at almost every level of linguistic organization. This fundamentally changes the object of enquiry from a cognitive science perspective. This target article summarizes decades of cross-linguistic work by typologists and descriptive linguists, showing just how few and unprofound the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • Language Structure: Psychological and Social Constraints.Gerhard Jäger & Robert van Rooij - 2007 - Synthese 159 (1):99 - 130.
    In this article we discuss the notion of a linguistic universal, and possible sources of such invariant properties of natural languages. In the first part, we explore the conceptual issues that arise. In the second part of the paper, we focus on the explanatory potential of horizontal evolution. We particularly focus on two case studies, concerning Zipf's Law and universal properties of color terms, respectively. We show how computer simulations can be employed to study the large scale, emergent, consequences of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Bound variables in syntax (Are there any?).Anna Szabolcsi - 1987 - In J. Groenendijk, F. Veltman & M. Stokhof (eds.), Sixth Amsterdam Colloquium Proceedings. Univ of Amserdam.
    Current theories of grammar handle both extraction and anaphorization by introducing variables into syntactic representations. Combinatory categorial grammar eliminates variables corresponding to gaps. Using the combinator W, the paper extends this approach to anaphors, which appear to act as overt bound variables. [Slightly extended version in Bartsch et al 1989.].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • New directions in type-theoretic grammars.Reinhard Muskens - 2010 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 19 (2):129-136.
    This paper argues for the idea that in describing language we should follow Haskell Curry in distinguishing between the structure of an expression and its appearance or manifestation . It is explained how making this distinction obviates the need for directed types in type-theoretic grammars and a simple grammatical formalism is sketched in which representations at all levels are lambda terms. The lambda term representing the abstract structure of an expression is homomorphically translated to a lambda term representing its manifestation, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue.Martin J. Pickering & Simon Garrod - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (2):169-190.
    Traditional mechanistic accounts of language processing derive almost entirely from the study of monologue. Yet, the most natural and basic form of language use is dialogue. As a result, these accounts may only offer limited theories of the mechanisms that underlie language processing in general. We propose a mechanistic account of dialogue, the interactive alignment account, and use it to derive a number of predictions about basic language processes. The account assumes that, in dialogue, the linguistic representations employed by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   260 citations  
  • Underspecified semantics.Reinhard Muskens - 2000 - In Klaus von Heusinger & Urs Egli (eds.), Reference and Anaphoric Relations. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 311--338.
    Ambiguities in natural language can multiply so fast that no person or machine can be expected to process a text of even moderate length by enumerating all possible disambiguations. A sentence containing $n$ scope bearing elements which are freely permutable will have $n!$ readings, if there are no other, say lexical or syntactic, sources of ambiguity. A series of $m$ such sentences would lead to $(n!)^m$ possibilities. All in all the growth of possibilities will be so fast that generating readings (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Higher order unification and the interpretation of focus.Stephen G. Pulman - 1997 - Linguistics and Philosophy 20 (1):73-115.
    Higher order unification is a way of combining information (or equivalently, solving equations) expressed as terms of a typed higher order logic. A suitably restricted form of the notion has been used as a simple and perspicuous basis for the resolution of the meaning of elliptical expressions and for the interpretation of some non-compositional types of comparative construction also involving ellipsis. This paper explores another area of application for this concept in the interpretation of sentences containing intonationally marked focus, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A grammar systems approach to natural language grammar.M. Dolores Jiménez López - 2006 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (4):419 - 454.
    Taking as its starting point significant similarities between a formal language model—Grammar Systems—and a grammatical theory—Autolexical Syntax—in this paper we suggest the application of the former to the topic of the latter. To show the applicability of Grammar Systems Theory to grammatical description, we introduce a formal-language-theoretic framework for the architecture of natural language grammar: Linguistic Grammar Systems. We prove the adequacy of this model by highlighting its features (modularity, parallelism, interaction) and by showing the similarity between this framework and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logic of unification in grammar.Robert T. Kasper & William C. Rounds - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (1):35 - 58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Introduction.Diego Gabriel Krivochen - 2021 - Evolutionary Linguistic Theory 3 (2):123-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reciprocal Influences Between Proof Theory and Logic Programming.Dale Miller - 2019 - Philosophy and Technology 34 (1):75-104.
    The topics of structural proof theory and logic programming have influenced each other for more than three decades. Proof theory has contributed the notion of sequent calculus, linear logic, and higher-order quantification. Logic programming has introduced new normal forms of proofs and forced the examination of logic-based approaches to the treatment of bindings. As a result, proof theory has responded by developing an approach to proof search based on focused proof systems in which introduction rules are organized into two alternating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Negative evidence” and the gratuitous leap from principles to parameters.James D. McCawley - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):627-628.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Displacement Calculus.Glyn Morrill, Oriol Valentín & Mario Fadda - 2011 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 20 (1):1-48.
    If all dependent expressions were adjacent some variety of immediate constituent analysis would suffice for grammar, but syntactic and semantic mismatches are characteristic of natural language; indeed this is a, or the, central problem in grammar. Logical categorial grammar reduces grammar to logic: an expression is well-formed if and only if an associated sequent is a theorem of a categorial logic. The paradigmatic categorial logic is the Lambek calculus, but being a logic of concatenation the Lambek calculus can only capture (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The processing of extraposed structures in English.Roger Levy, Evelina Fedorenko, Mara Breen & Edward Gibson - 2012 - Cognition 122 (1):12-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • With diversity in mind: Freeing the language sciences from Universal Grammar.Nicholas Evans & Stephen C. Levinson - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (5):472-492.
    Our response takes advantage of the wide-ranging commentary to clarify some aspects of our original proposal and augment others. We argue against the generative critics of our coevolutionary program for the language sciences, defend the use of close-to-surface models as minimizing cross-linguistic data distortion, and stress the growing role of stochastic simulations in making generalized historical accounts testable. These methods lead the search for general principles away from idealized representations and towards selective processes. Putting cultural evolution central in understanding language (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Complexity in Language Acquisition.Alexander Clark & Shalom Lappin - 2013 - Topics in Cognitive Science 5 (1):89-110.
    Learning theory has frequently been applied to language acquisition, but discussion has largely focused on information theoretic problems—in particular on the absence of direct negative evidence. Such arguments typically neglect the probabilistic nature of cognition and learning in general. We argue first that these arguments, and analyses based on them, suffer from a major flaw: they systematically conflate the hypothesis class and the learnable concept class. As a result, they do not allow one to draw significant conclusions about the learner. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Principled Approach to Grammars for Controlled Natural Languages and Predictive Editors.Tobias Kuhn - 2013 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 22 (1):33-70.
    Controlled natural languages (CNL) with a direct mapping to formal logic have been proposed to improve the usability of knowledge representation systems, query interfaces, and formal specifications. Predictive editors are a popular approach to solve the problem that CNLs are easy to read but hard to write. Such predictive editors need to be able to “look ahead” in order to show all possible continuations of a given unfinished sentence. Such lookahead features, however, are difficult to implement in a satisfying way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2010 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6 (1).
    Formal semantics is an approach to SEMANTICS1, the study of meaning, with roots in logic, the philosophy of language, and linguistics, and since the 1980’s a core area of linguistic theory. Characteristics of formal semantics to be treated in this article include the following: Formal semanticists treat meaning as mind-independent (though abstract), contrasting with the view of meanings as concepts “in the head” (see I-LANGUAGE AND E-LANGUAGE and MEANING EXTERNALISM AND INTERNALISM); formal semanticists distinguish semantics from knowledge of semantics (Lewis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Lexicalised Locality: Local Domains and Non-Local Dependencies in a Lexicalised Tree Adjoining Grammar.Diego Gabriel Krivochen & Andrea Padovan - 2021 - Philosophies 6 (3):70.
    Contemporary generative grammar assumes that syntactic structure is best described in terms of sets, and that locality conditions, as well as cross-linguistic variation, is determined at the level of designated functional heads. Syntactic operations (merge, MERGE, etc.) build a structure by deriving sets from lexical atoms and recursively (and monotonically) yielding sets of sets. Additional restrictions over the format of structural descriptions limit the number of elements involved in each operation to two at each derivational step, a head and a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge-based disambiguation for machine translation.Joachim Quantz & Birte Schmitz - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (1):39-57.
    The resolution of ambiguities is one of the central problems for Machine Translation. In this paper we propose a knowledge-based approach to disambiguation which uses Description Logics (dl) as representation formalism. We present the process of anaphora resolution implemented in the Machine Translation systemfast and show how thedl systemback is used to support disambiguation.The disambiguation strategy uses factors representing syntactic, semantic, and conceptual constraints with different weights to choose the most adequate antecedent candidate. We show how these factors can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From word to sentence: A pregroup analysis of the object pronoun who ( M ). [REVIEW]J. Lambek - 2007 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 16 (3):303-323.
    We explore a computational algebraic approach to grammar via pregroups, that is, partially ordered monoids in which each element has both a left and a right adjoint. Grammatical judgements are formed with the help of calculations on types. These are elements of the free pregroup generated by a partially ordered set of basic types, which are assigned to words, here of English. We concentrate on the object pronoun who(m).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unbounded reflexives.Beom-Mo Kang - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (4):415 - 456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ellipsis and higher-order unification.Mary Dalrymple, Stuart M. Shieber & Fernando C. N. Pereira - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (4):399 - 452.
    We present a new method for characterizing the interpretive possibilities generated by elliptical constructions in natural language. Unlike previous analyses, which postulate ambiguity of interpretation or derivation in the full clause source of the ellipsis, our analysis requires no such hidden ambiguity. Further, the analysis follows relatively directly from an abstract statement of the ellipsis interpretation problem. It predicts correctly a wide range of interactions between ellipsis and other semantic phenomena such as quantifier scope and bound anaphora. Finally, although the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Cross-linguistic evidence for memory storage costs in filler-gap dependencies with wh-adjuncts.Artur Stepanov & Penka Stateva - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:145572.
    This study investigates processing of interrogative filler-gap dependencies in which the filler integration site or gap is not directly subcategorized by the verb. This is the case when the wh-filler is a structural adjunct such as how or when rather than subject or object. Two self-paced reading experiments in English and Slovenian provide converging cross-linguistic evidence that wh-adjuncts elicit a kind of memory storage cost similar to that previously shown in the literature for wh-arguments. Experiment 1 investigates the storage costs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Head-driven phrase structure grammar: linguistic approach, formal foundations, and computational realization.Robert D. Levine & W. Detmar Meurers - 2005 - In Keith Brown (ed.), Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. Elsevier.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Parameter setting and early emergence.Amy Weinberg - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):637-638.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • We need a team of gene-mappers, not principle-provers.Thomas Roeper - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):630-631.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nature of the memory buffer in implicit learning: Learning Chinese tonal symmetries.Feifei Li, Shan Jiang, Xiuyan Guo, Zhiliang Yang & Zoltan Dienes - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (3):920-930.
    Previous research has established that people can implicitly learn chunks, which do not require a memory buffer to process. The present study explores the implicit learning of nonlocal dependencies generated by higher than finite-state grammars, specifically, Chinese tonal retrogrades and inversions , which do require buffers . People were asked to listen to and memorize artificial poetry instantiating one of the two grammars; after this training phase, people were informed of the existence of rules and asked to classify new poems, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why cognitive science is not formalized folk psychology.Martin Pickering & Nick Chater - 1995 - Minds and Machines 5 (3):309-337.
    It is often assumed that cognitive science is built upon folk psychology, and that challenges to folk psychology are therefore challenges to cognitive science itself. We argue that, in practice, cognitive science and folk psychology treat entirely non-overlapping domains: cognitive science considers aspects of mental life which do not depend on general knowledge, whereas folk psychology considers aspects of mental life which do depend on general knowledge. We back up our argument on theoretical grounds, and also illustrate the separation between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Phrase structure parameters.Janet Dean Fodor & Stephen Crain - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (6):619-659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Editors' Introduction: Miscommunication.Patrick G. T. Healey, Jan P. de Ruiter & Gregory J. Mills - 2018 - Topics in Cognitive Science 10 (2):264-278.
    Healey et al. introduce the special issue with a brief overview of work on communication in the Cognitive Sciences and some of the historical and conceptual influences that have marginalized the study of miscommunication. Drawing on more recent work in Cognitive Science and Conversation Analysis they argue that miscommunication is in fact a highly structured, ubiquitous phenomenon that is fundamental to human interaction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Introduction to the Special Issue Honoring the 2014 David E. Rumelhart Prize Recipient, Ray Jackendoff.Peter W. Culicover - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S2):213-232.
    In Jackendoff's Parallel Architecture, the well-formed expressions of a language are licensed by correspondences between phonology, syntax, and conceptual structure. I show how this architecture can be used to make sense of the existence of parasitic gap constructions. A parasitic gap is one that is rendered acceptable because of the presence of another gap in the same sentence. Compare *a person who everyone who talks to likes Chris, which shows an illicit extraction from a relative clause, and a person everyone (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • It is there whether you hear it or not: Syntactic representation of missing arguments.Zhenguang G. Cai, Martin J. Pickering, Ruiming Wang & Holly P. Branigan - 2015 - Cognition 136 (C):255-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Expectation-based syntactic comprehension.Roger Levy - 2008 - Cognition 106 (3):1126-1177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   204 citations  
  • Charting the course of language development.Stephen Crain - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):639-650.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Early emergence as a diagnostic for innateness.Laurence B. Leonard - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):625-626.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Debatable constraints.Thomas Wasow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):636-637.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Simians, space, and syntax: Parallels between human language and primate social cognition.Leslie Brothers & Michael J. Raleigh - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):613-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:13.
    Formal semantics and pragmatics as they have developed since the late 1960's have been shaped by fruitful interdisciplinary collaboration among linguists, philosophers, and logicians, among others, and in turn have had noticeable effects on developments in syntax, philosophy of language, computational linguistics, and cognitive science.In this paper I describe the environment in which formal semantics was born and took root, highlighting the differences in ways of thinking about natural language semantics in linguistics and in philosophy and logic. With Montague as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Compositionality as an empirical problem.David Dowty - 2007 - In Chris Barker & Pauline I. Jacobson (eds.), Direct compositionality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 14--23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Computational structure of GPSG models.Eric Sven Ristad - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (5):521 - 587.
    The primary goal of this essay is to demonstrate how considerations from computational complexity theory can inform grammatical theorizing. To this end, generalized phrase structure grammar (GPSG) linguistic theory is revised so that its power more closely matches the limited ability of an ideal speaker-hearer: GPSG Recognition is EXP-POLY time hard, while Revised GPSG Recognition is NP-complete. A second goal is to provide a theoretical framework within which to better understand the wide range of existing GPSG models, embodied in formal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Did Frege believe Frege's principle?Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 2001 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10 (1):87-114.
    In this essay I will consider two theses that are associated with Frege,and will investigate the extent to which Frege really believed them.Much of what I have to say will come as no surprise to scholars of thehistorical Frege. But Frege is not only a historical figure; he alsooccupies a site on the philosophical landscape that has allowed hisdoctrines to seep into the subconscious water table. And scholars in a widevariety of different scholarly establishments then sip from thesedoctrines. I believe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Unification grammars and off-line parsability.Efrat Jaeger, Nissim Francez & Shuly Wintner - 2005 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14 (2):199-234.
    Unification grammars are known to be Turing-equivalent; given a grammar G and a word w, it is undecidable whether w L(G). In order to ensure decidability, several constraints on grammars, commonly known as off-line parsability (OLP), were suggested, such that the recognition problem is decidable for grammars which satisfy OLP. An open question is whether it is decidable if a given grammar satisfies OLP. In this paper we investigate various definitions of OLP and discuss their interrelations, proving that some of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Geach’s Categorial Grammar.Lloyd Humberstone - 2004 - Linguistics and Philosophy 28 (3):281 - 317.
    Geach’s rich paper ‘A Program for Syntax’ introduced many ideas into the arena of categorial grammar, not all of which have been given the attention they warrant in the thirty years since its first publication. Rather surprisingly, one of our findings (Section 3 below) is that the paper not only does not contain a statement of what has widely come to be known as “Geach’s Rule”, but in fact presents considerations which are inimical to the adoption of the rule in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Jacobson on GKPS: A rejoinder. [REVIEW]Thomas Hukari & Robert D. Levine - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (3):363 - 381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Referentiality and Configurationality in the Idiom and the Phrasal Verb.Cem Bozşahin - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (2):175-207.
    Two positions of Bolinger, about synonymy and meaningfulness of words, point to significance of controlling the referentiality of word forms, from representing them in grammar to their projection onto surface structure, i.e. configurationality. In particular, it becomes critical to control the range of surface substitution for surface syntactic categories of words to maintain referential properties of idiosyncrasy. Categorial grammars as reference systems suggest ways to keep the two aspects in grammar. The first dividend of adopting a categorial perspective is systematically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Syntactic codes and grammar refinement.Marcus Kracht - 1995 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 4 (1):41-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations