Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The λ model: Can it walk?Aftab E. Patla - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):775-776.
    Generation of swing phase limb trajectory over obstacles during locomotion should be a reasonable test for the λ model proposed by Feldman and Levin. The observed features such as lack of simple amplitude scaling of endpoint (toe) trajectories for different obstacle heights, complex shaped toe velocity profiles, and exploitation of passive intersegmental dynamics to control limb elevation cannot be adequately explained by the λ model.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modeling Sensory Preference in Speech Motor Planning: A Bayesian Modeling Framework.Jean-François Patri, Julien Diard & Pascal Perrier - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Experimental studies of speech production involving compensations for auditory and somatosensory perturbations and adaptation after training suggest that both types of sensory information are considered to plan and monitor speech production. Interestingly, individual sensory preferences have been observed in this context: subjects who compensate less for somatosensory perturbations compensate more for auditory perturbations, and \textit{vice versa}. We propose to integrate this sensory preference phenomenon in a model of speech motor planning using a probabilistic model in which speech units are characterized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Architectonic Experience of Body and Space in Augmented Interiors.Isabella Pasqualini, Maria Laura Blefari, Tej Tadi, Andrea Serino & Olaf Blanke - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quantifying the Degree of Movement Dissimilarity between Two Distinct Action Scenarios: An Exploratory Approach with Procrustes Analysis.Pedro Passos, Tania Campos & Ana Diniz - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Simultaneous processing of features may not be possible.D. M. Parker - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):411-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Let us accept a “controlled trade-off” model of motor control.Lloyd D. Partridge - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):773-775.
    The trade-off between force and length of muscle as adjusted by neural signals is a critical fact in the dynamics of motor control. Whether we call it “length-tension effect,” “feedback-like,” “invariant condition,” or “spring-like” is unimportant. We must not let semantics or details of representation obscure the basic physics of effects introduced by this trade-off in muscle.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How was movement controlled before Newton?Lloyd D. Partridge - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):561-561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Frogs solve Bernstein's problem.Lloyd D. Partridge - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):619-620.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Enhanced Memory for Fair-Related Faces and the Role of Trait Anxiety.Gewnhi Park, Benjamin U. Marsh & Elisha J. Johnson - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    The current research examined whether fair consideration—a social norm that people inherently prefer to confirm—would modulate face recognition. Each neutral face was associated with fair offers or unfair offers via an economic decision task, the Ultimatum Game (UG) task. After the UG, participants were asked to identify the faces of proposers who made different offers. Enhanced memory was observed for fair-related faces compared to unfair-related faces. Furthermore, high trait anxiety was associated with reduced memory for fair-related faces. These results were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Comment: Journeys to the Center of Emotion.Brian Parkinson - 2013 - Emotion Review 5 (2):180-184.
    Does appraisal co-ordinate emotional responses? Are emotions usually reached via mental representations of relational meaning? This comment considers alternative causal routes in order to assess the centrality of appraisal in the explanation of emotion. Implicit and explicit meaning extraction can certainly help steer the course of emotion-related processes. However, presupposing that appraisals represent the driving force behind all aspects of emotion generation leads to inclusive formulations of appraisal or restrictive formulations of emotion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • When Neuroscience ‘Touches’ Architecture: From Hapticity to a Supramodal Functioning of the Human Brain.Paolo Papale, Leonardo Chiesi, Alessandra C. Rampinini, Pietro Pietrini & Emiliano Ricciardi - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7:186785.
    In the last decades, the rapid growth of functional brain imaging methodologies allowed cognitive neuroscience to address open questions in philosophy and the social sciences. At the same time, novel insights from cognitive neuroscience research have begun to influence various disciplines, leading to a turn to cognition and emotion in the fields of planning and architectural design. Since 2003, the Academy of Neuroscience for Architecture has been supporting ‘neuro-architecture’ as a way to connect neuroscience and the study of behavioral responses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extending Research on Deception in Sport – Combining Perception and Kinematic Approaches.Josefine Panten, Florian Loffing, Joseph Baker & Jörg Schorer - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Architecture and connections of the premotor areas in the rhesus monkey.Deepak N. Pandya & Helen Barbas - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):595-596.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Operationaling “correspondence”.David C. Palmer - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):206-207.
    The research guided by the correspondence metaphor is lauded for its emphasis on functional analysis, but the term “correspondence” itself needs clarification. Of the two terms in the relationship, only one is well defined. It is suggested that behavior at acquisition needs to be analyzed and that molecular principles from the learning laboratory might be useful in doing so.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What spaces? What subjects?Jean Pailhous & Patrick Peruch - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):646-647.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The perceptual stability of the visual field: What is calibration for?Jacques Paillard, Michelle Fleury, Normand Teasdale, Chantal Bard & Vincent Nougier - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):272-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jeannerod's representing brain: Image or illusion?Jean Pailhous & Mireille Bonnard - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):215-216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • When Poetry and Phenomenology Collide.Jeremy Page - 2018 - Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 5 (1):31-51.
    In recent years several scholars have wrestled with the term “poetic thought,” suggesting in various ways there is something distinctive about the nature of meaning as it occurs/unfolds through poetry. In this paper I suggest, in part following the lead of Simon Jarvis, that one of the most fruitful lines of inquiry for exploring this idea lies in a consideration of poetic works through the lens of Heidegger’s early phenomenology. Specifically, I argue that one of the keys to understanding poetic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spatial frames for motor control would be commensurate with spatial frames for vision and proprioception, but what about control of energy flows?Christopher C. Pagano & Geoffrey P. Bingham - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):773-773.
    The model identifies a spatial coordinate frame within which the sensorimotor apparatus produces movement. Its spatial nature simplifies its coupling with spatial reference frames used concurrently by vision and proprioception. While the positional reference frame addresses the performance of spatial tasks, it seems to have little to say about movements involving energy expenditure as the principle component of the task.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The content of intentions.Elisabeth Patherie - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (4):400-432.
    I argue that in order to solve the main difficulties confronted by the classical versions of the causal theory of action, it is necessary no just to make room for intentions, considered as irreducible to complexes of beliefs and desires, but also to distinguish among several types of intentions. I present a three-tiered theory of intentions that distinguishes among future-directed intentions, present-directed intentions and motor intentions. I characterize each kind of intention in terms of its functions, its type of content, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Taxonomy is older than thinking: Epigenetic decisions.Andrew Packard - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):296-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Search Strategies in the Perceptual-Motor Workspace and the Acquisition of Coordination, Control, and Skill.Matheus M. Pacheco, Charley W. Lafe & Karl M. Newell - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Do we see with microscopes?Elisabeth Pacherie - 1995 - The Monist 78 (2):171-188.
    Trying to understand better the role played by epistemic artifacts in our quest for reliable knowledge, it is interesting to compare their contribution with the one made by the epistemic organs or systems with which we are naturally endowed. This comparative approach may yield the further benefit of an improved understanding of the nature and epistemic functions of our natural epistemic equipment. In this paper, I shall concern myself with comparing the role of a family of instruments, microscopes, with that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Calls as labels: An intriguing theme, but one with limitations.Donald H. Owings - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):162-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Seeing where we look: Fixation as extraretinal information.D. Alfred Owens & Edward S. Reed - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):271-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Enactivism and the Perception of Others’ Emotions.Søren Overgaard - 2017 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41 (1):105-129.
    According to ‘direct social perception’ (DSP) accounts of social cognition, perception may be ‘smart’ enough on its own to inform us about other people’s emotions. Some DSP advocates suggest that ‘smart’ social perception should be conceived along ‘enactive’ lines. In this paper, I suggest that DSP needs social perception to have representational content. This seems in tension with the main versions of enactivism, which deny that perception is representational. I thus present the following challenge to ‘enactive’ versions of DSP: either (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Concepts and how they get that way.Karenleigh A. Overmann - 2019 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18 (1):153-168.
    Drawing on the material culture of the Ancient Near East as interpreted through Material Engagement Theory, the journey of how material number becomes a conceptual number is traced to address questions of how a particular material form might generate a concept and how concepts might ultimately encompass multiple material forms so that they include but are irreducible to all of them together. Material forms incorporated into the cognitive system affect the content and structure of concepts through their agency and affordances, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Command invariants and the frame of reference for human movement.David J. Ostry, Rafael Laboissière & Paul L. Gribble - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):770-772.
    We describe a solution to the redundancy problem related to that proposed in Feldman & Levin's target article. We suggest that the system may use a fixed mapping between commands organized at the level of degrees of freedom and commands to individual muscles. This proposal eliminates the need to maintain an explicit representation of musculoskeletalgeometry in planning movements.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can voluntary movement be understood on the basis of reflex organization?David J. Ostry & Frances E. Wilkinson - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):618-619.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Brain damage and cognitive dysfunction.Marlene Oscar-Berman - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):678-679.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The distribution of representation.Lisa M. Osbeck & Nancy J. Nersessian - 2006 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 36 (2):141–160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Creative Motor Actions As Emerging from Movement Variability.Dominic Orth, John van der Kamp, Daniel Memmert & Geert J. P. Savelsbergh - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Behavioral Repertoire Influences the Rate and Nature of Learning in Climbing: Implications for Individualized Learning Design in Preparation for Extreme Sports Participation.Dominic Orth, Keith Davids, Jia-Yi Chow, Eric Brymer & Ludovic Seifert - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The world as an outside iconic memory – no strong internal metric means no problem of visual stability.J. Kevin O'Regan - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):270-271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What do double dissociations prove?Guy C. Orden, Bruce F. Pennington & Gregory O. Stone - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (1):111-172.
    Brain damage may doubly dissociate cognitive modules, but the practice of revealing dissociations is predicated on modularity being true (T. Shallice, 1988). This article questions the utility of assuming modularity, as it examines a paradigmatic double dissociation of reading modules. Reading modules illustrate two general problems. First, modularity fails to converge on a fixed set of exclusionary criteria that define pure cases. As a consequence, competing modular theories force perennial quests for purer cases, which simply perpetuates growth in the list (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • An enactive account of placebo effects.Giulio Ongaro & Dave Ward - 2017 - Biology and Philosophy 32 (4):507-533.
    Placebos are commonly defined as ineffective treatments. They are treatments that lack a known mechanism linking their properties to the properties of the condition on which treatment aims to intervene. Given this, the fact that placebos can have substantial therapeutic effects looks puzzling. The puzzle, we argue, arises from the relationship placebos present between culturally meaningful entities, our intentional relationship to the environment and bodily effects. How can a mere attitude toward a treatment result in appropriate bodily changes? We argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What Ekman really said.Mats Olsson, Kathleen Harder & John C. Baird - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):157-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The role of concepts in perception and inference.David R. Olson & Janet Wilde Astington - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):65-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Spatial development.David R. Olson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):249-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural learning and educational process.David R. Olson & Janet Wilde Astington - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):531-532.
    Tomasello, Kruger & Ratner relate the evolution of social cognition – the understanding of others' minds – to the evolution of culture. Tomasello et al. conceive of the accumulation of culture as the product of cultural learning, a kind of learning dependent upon recognizing others' intentionality. They distinguish three levels of this recognition: of intention (what isxtrying to do), of beliefs (what doesxthink aboutp), and of beliefs about beliefs (what doesxthinkythinks aboutp). They then tie these levels to three discrete forms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Units “of” selection: The end of “of”?F. J. Odling-Smee & H. C. Plotkin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):295-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Space of Motivations.Donnchadh O’Conaill - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (3):440-455.
    The distinction between the space of reasons and the realm of law captures two familiar ways of making events intelligible, by reference to reasons or to natural laws, respectively. I describe a third way of making events intelligible, by explaining them in terms of an agent’s being motivated to do certain things. Explanations of this sort do not involve appealing to reasons for which the agent acts, nor to natural laws under which the event falls. To explain an event in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Embodiment and the Construction of Social Knowledge: Towards an Integration of Embodiment and Social Representations Theory.Cliodhna O'Connor - 2017 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 47 (1):2-24.
    Recent developments in the psychological and social sciences have seen a surge of attention to concepts of embodiment. The burgeoning field of embodied cognition, as well as the long-standing tradition of phenomenological philosophy, offer valuable insights for theorising how people come to understand the world around them. However, the implications of human embodiment have been largely neglected by one of the key frameworks for conceptualising the development of social knowledge: Social Representations Theory. This article seeks to spark a dialogue between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Subjects and Objects: Metaphysics, Biology, Consciousness, and Cognition.Seán Ó. Nualláin - 2008 - Biosemiotics 1 (2):239-251.
    Over the past half-century, the Freeman laboratory has accumulated a large volume of data and a correspondingly extensive interpretive framework centered around an alternative perspective on brain function, that of dynamical systems. The purpose of this paper is first briefly to summarise this work, and bring it into dialogue with other perspectives. The contents of consciousness are seen as an inevitably sparse sample of events in the perception–action cycle. The paper proceeds to an attempt to elucidate the contents of this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Moments of recognition: deontic power and bodily felt demands.Henning Nörenberg - 2020 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 19 (1):191-206.
    While the current discussion on embodied cognition provides valuable accounts of an agent’s bodily sensitivity to instrumental possibilities, in this paper I investigate felt demands as the bodily-affective dimension of the agent’s recognition of deontic powers such as obligations. I argue that there is a close kinship between felt demands and affordances in the stricter sense. I will suggest that what is unique about felt demands on an experiential level is that they involve an evaluative perspective arising from acute or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context effects in the entropic theory of perception.Kenneth H. Norwich - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-579.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What exists in the environment that motivates the emergence, transmission, and sophistication of tool use?Tetsushi Nonaka & Krist Vaesen - 2012 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35 (4):233.
    In his attempt to find cognitive traits that set humans apart from nonhuman primates with respect to tool use, Vaesen overlooks the primacy of the environment toward the use of which behavior evolves. The occurrence of a particular behavior is a result of how that behavior has evolved in a complex and changing environment selected by a unique population.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Time from Semiosis: E-series Time for Living Systems.Naoki Nomura, Tomoaki Muranaka, Jun Tomita & Koichiro Matsuno - 2018 - Biosemiotics 11 (1):65-83.
    We develop a semiotic scheme of time, in which time precipitates from the repeated succession of punctuating the progressive tense by the perfect tense. The underlying principle is communication among local participants. Time can thus be seen as a meaning-making, semiotic system in which different time codes are delineated, each having its own grammar and timekeeping. The four time codes discussed are the following: the subjective time having tense, the objective time without tense, the static time without timekeeping, and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What are mental states?William Noble & Iain Davidson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):162-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action and The Embodied Mind, by Andy Clark.Alva Noë - 2018 - Mind 127 (506):611-618.
    Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action and The Embodied Mind, by ClarkAndy. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2016.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation