Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Précis of Writing the Book of the World.Theodore Sider - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87 (3):706-708.
    This is a symposium on my book, Writing the Book of the World, containing a precis from me, criticisms from Dorr, Fine, and Hirsch, and replies by me.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A problem for representationalist versions of extended cognition.Pierre Steiner - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (2):184-202.
    In order to account for how organisms can apprehend the contents of the external representations they manipulate in cognizing, the endorsement of representationalism fosters a situation of what I call cognitive overdetermination. I argue that this situation is problematic for the inclusion of these external representations in cognitive processing, as the hypothesis of extended cognition would like to have it. Since that situation arises from a commitment to representationalism (even minimal), it only affects the viability of representationalist versions of extended (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Genealogy, Epistemology and Worldmaking.Amia Srinivasan - 2019 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 119 (2):127-156.
    We suffer from genealogical anxiety when we worry that the contingent origins of our representations, once revealed, will somehow undermine or cast doubt on those representations. Is such anxiety ever rational? Many have apparently thought so, from pre-Socratic critics of Greek theology to contemporary evolutionary debunkers of morality. One strategy for vindicating critical genealogies is to see them as undermining the epistemic standing of our representations—the justification of our beliefs, the aptness of our concepts, and so on. I argue that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • You Are Not Your Brain: Against 'Teaching to the Brain'.Gregory M. Nixon - 2012 - Review of Higher Education and Self-Learning 5 (15):69-83.
    Since educators are always looking for ways to improve their practice, and since empirical science is now accepted in our worldview as the final arbiter of truth, it is no surprise they have been lured toward cognitive neuroscience in hopes that discovering how the brain learns will provide a nutshell explanation for student learning in general. I argue that identifying the person with the brain is scientism (not science), that the brain is not the person, and that it is the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain.Daniel C. Dennett & Marcel Kinsbourne - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):183-201.
    _Behavioral and Brain Sciences_ , 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in _The Philosopher's Annual_ , Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994, pp. 23-68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., _Cognitive Science_ , Vol. I, Elgar, 1995, pp.210-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   376 citations  
  • Escape from the Cartesian Theater.Daniel C. Dennett & Marcel Kinsbourne - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):234-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Counting consciousnesses: None, one, two, or none of the above?Daniel C. Dennett & Marcel Kinsbourne - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):178.
    In a second there is also time enough, we might add. In his dichotomizing fervor, Bogen fails to realize that our argument is neutral with respect to the number of consciousnesses that inhabit the normal or the split-brain skull. Should there be two, for instance, we would point out that within the neural network that subserves each, no privileged locus should be postulated. (Midline location is not the issue--it was only a minor issue for Descartes, in fact.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The how and why of what went where in apparent motion: Modeling solutions to the motion correspondence problem.Michael R. Dawson - 1991 - Psychological Review 98 (4):569-603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Putnam’s Brain-Teaser.David Davies - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):203--27.
    1. Metaphysical Realists have traditionally relied upon the skeptic to give substance to the idea that truth is, in the words of Hilary Putnam, 'radically non-episternic,’ forever outstripping, in principle at least, the reach of justification. What better model of truth so conceived, after all, than the skeptic's contention that even our firmest convictions might be mistaken in that we might be the victims of demonic deception or the machinations of an evil scientist? But the availability of this favorite model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the need for a computational psychology and the hope for a naturalistic one.Lawrence H. Davis - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):76-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deferred action: Irish neo-avant-garde poetry.Alex Davis - 2000 - Angelaki 5 (1):81 – 93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Traveller's Guide to Putnam's “Narrow Path”. [REVIEW]David Davies - 1996 - Dialogue 35 (1):117-146.
    It is now over 15 years since Hilary Putnam first urged that we take the “narrow path” of internal realism as a way of navigating between “the swamps of metaphysics and the quicksands of cultural relativism and historicism” (1983, p. 226). In the opening lines of the Preface toRealism with a Human Face, a collection of Putnam's recent papers edited by James Conant, Putnam reaffirms his allegiance to this narrow path, unmoved by Realist murmurings from the swamps and laconic Rortian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The selfless consciousness.Antonio R. Damasio - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):208-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Causes and representation.Robert Cummins - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):76-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Many Faces of Science and Technology Relationships.Ana Cuevas - 2005 - Essays in Philosophy 6 (1):54-75.
    In this paper, the different theories about science and technology relationships are analyzed. All of them have some virtues, but also one main defect: these theories do not take into account other well-founded possible relationships. The origin of this problem is the narrow view about science and technology. In this paper another characterization about technology based on Ronald Giere’s perspective is suggested. In the light of this new description, six different relationships between science and technology arise. Some of these relations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malthus and Ricardo: Two styles for Economic Theory.Sergio Cremaschi & Marcelo Dascal - 1998 - Science in Context 11 (2):229-254.
    We examine the most famous controversy between economists as a means of shedding fresh light on the current debate about economic methodology. By focusing on the controversy as the primary unit of analysis, we show how methodological considerations are but one of a whole set of stratagems strategically employed by each opponent. We argue that each opponent's preference for a particular kind of stratagems expresses his own specific scientific style (within the general scientific and cultural style of an age). We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Failed States in Education: Chomsky on Dissent, Propaganda, and Reclaiming Democracy in the Media Spectacle.Aaron Cooley - 2010 - Educational Studies: A Jrnl of the American Educ. Studies Assoc 46 (6):579-605.
    This paper discusses the work of Noam Chomsky in the context of democracy, the media, and education. Through the analysis of selected works, a critical perspective emerges. This view demands that educators at all levels understand and confront the often deleterious effects the media can have on students' social and political views and further how the media can undermine democratic action in schools and society.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some defects in Fodor' ‘computational’ theory.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is menstruation for? On the projectibility of functional predicates in menstruation research.S. Clough - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):719-732.
    In 1993, biologist Margie Profet captured the attention of the popular press with the publication of her radical thesis: menstruation has a function. Traditional theories, she claims, typically view menstruation as a functionless by-product of cyclic flux. The details of Profet's functional account are similarly radical: she argues that menstruation has been naturally selected to defend the female reproductive tract from sperm-borne pathogens. There are a number of weaknesses in Profet's evolutionary analysis. However, I focus on a set of pragmatic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Experiential facts?Andy Clark - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):207-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In defense of naturalism.Paul M. Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):74-75.
    History and the modern sciences are characterized by what is sometimes called a “methodological naturalism” that disregards talk of divine agency. Some religious thinkers argue that this reflects a dogmatic materialism: a non-negotiable and a priori commitment to a materialist metaphysics. In response to this charge, I make a sharp distinction between procedural requirements and metaphysical commitments. The procedural requirement of history and the sciences—that proposed explanations appeal to publicly-accessible bodies of evidence—is non-negotiable, but has no metaphysical implications. The metaphysical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dispositions: An Integrational Analysis.Daihyun Chung - 2017 - Diogenes:59-70.
    Whereas the Humean accounts of causality in terms of contiguity, temporal priority, constant conjunction, and contingency face difficulties of one sort, the dispositional explanations of causality...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Some aspirin for Dasein.Eugene Charniak - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):74-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • About continuity and rupture in the history of chemistry: the fourth chemical revolution.José A. Chamizo - 2018 - Foundations of Chemistry 21 (1):11-29.
    A layered interpretation of the history of chemistry is discussed through chemical revolutions. A chemical revolution mainly by emplacement, instead of replacement, procedures were identified by: a radical reinterpretation of existing thought recognized by contemporaries themselves, which means the appearance of new concepts and the arrival of new theories; the use of new instruments changed the way in which its practitioners looked and worked in the world and through exemplars, new entities were discovered or incorporated; the opening of new subdisciplines, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Complex Global Microstructures.Karin Knorr Cetina - 2005 - Theory, Culture and Society 22 (5):213-234.
    The new terrorism is a major exemplifying case for complexity theory – for example, it exemplifies major disproportionalities between cause and effect, unpredictable outcomes, and self-organizing, emergent structures. It also illustrates, I argue in this article, the emergence of global microstructures: of forms of connectivity and coordination that combine global reach with microstructural mechanisms that instantiate self-organizing principles and patterns. Global systems based on microstructural principles do not exhibit institutional complexity but rather the asymmetries, unpredictabilities and playfulness of complex (and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • ¿Cómo construir cuerpos individuales en el universo cartesiano?Carlos Alberto Cardona Suárez & Juan Raúl Loaiza Arias - 2016 - Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 33 (2):489-515.
    En el presente artículo se muestra que en la cosmología cartesiana no resulta claro cómo se puede hablar o referir a cuerpos individuales en el marco de un universo absolutamente compacto. Se defiende que el concepto de cuerpo individual en el interior de dicha cosmología se puede construir como una ficción del espíritu. Un cuerpo individual se puede construir como la extensión que se encuentra encerrada en una superficie maximal cuyas subdivisiones carecen de movimiento relativo entre sí. Se muestra, también, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Critical Examination of the New Sociology of Science Part 2.Mario Bunge - 1992 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 22 (1):46-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The artful mind meets art history: Toward a psycho-historical framework for the science of art appreciation.Nicolas J. Bullot & Rolf Reber - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (2):123-137.
    Research seeking a scientific foundation for the theory of art appreciation has raised controversies at the intersection of the social and cognitive sciences. Though equally relevant to a scientific inquiry into art appreciation, psychological and historical approaches to art developed independently and lack a common core of theoretical principles. Historicists argue that psychological and brain sciences ignore the fact that artworks are artifacts produced and appreciated in the context of unique historical situations and artistic intentions. After revealing flaws in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Democracy, Religion and Revolution.Craig Browne - 2009 - Thesis Eleven 99 (1):27-47.
    Charles Taylor’s conception of the relationship between democracy and social creativity developed through a critical synthesis of various traditions, including the Romantic Movement and liberal political philosophy. However, it is argued that Taylor’s understanding of the implications of religion and revolution significantly differentiates his standpoint from that of pragmatism and theories of democratic creativity. Taylor’s defence of religious transcendence is shown to give rise to tensions with the latter perspective. The theorists of democratic creativity suggest that democracy originates in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What is consciousness for, anyway?Bruce Bridgeman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):206-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Sporting Exploration of the World; Toward a Fundamental Ontology of the Sporting Human Being.Gunnar Breivik - 2019 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 14 (2):146-162.
    My perspective in this paper is to look at sport and other physical activities as a way of exploring and experimenting with the environing world. The human being is basically the homo movens – born...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • German Philosophy Today: Between Idealism, Romanticism, and Pragmatism.Andrew Bowie - 1999 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 44:357-398.
    In his essayOn the History of Religion and Philosophy in Germany, of 1834, Heinrich Heine suggested to his French audience that the German propensity for ‘metaphysical abstractions’ had led many people to condemn philosophy for its failure to have a practical effect, Germany having only had its revolution in thought, while France had its in reality. Heine, albeit somewhat ironically, refuses to join those who condemn philosophy: ‘German philosophy is an important matter, which concerns the whole of humanity, and only (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Social space and symbolic power.Pierre Bourdieu - 1989 - Sociological Theory 7 (1):14-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Fragments of illness: The Death of a Beekeeper as a literary case study of cancer.Hilde Bondevik, Knut Stene-Johansen & Rolf Ahlzén - 2016 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 19 (2):275-283.
    The first decisive steps of medicine towards becoming a science in its present shape happen to coincide with “the rise of the novel” in the eighteenth century. Before this well known and in our days still growing scientific specialization of medicine, the connections between literature and medicine were both many and close. By reading and analyzing a contemporary novel, The Death of a Beekeeper by the Swedish author Lars Gustafsson, this article is an attempt to explore to which extent a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Descartes' fundamental mistake: Introspective singularity.Joseph E. Bogen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):175-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Back in Style: A New Interpretation of Danto's Style Matrix.Frank Boardman - 2015 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4):441-448.
    A number of objections to the style matrix that Arthur Danto introduced in “The Artworld” seem to have quelled most discussion of it. So telling have these arguments been that Danto himself later recanted the idea entirely. This situation is somewhat unfortunate. It may be that Danto's own interpretation of the style matrix is not tenable, but I believe we can articulate an alternative reading of it that escapes the aforementioned objections. While the interpretation I suggest cannot provide all that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • States' rights.Ned Block & Sylvain Bromberger - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):73-74.
    This is a response to Jerry Fodor’s article, Fodor, J. (1980). "Methodological solipsism as a research strategy in cognitive psychology." Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 63-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Begging the question against phenomenal consciousness.Ned Block - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):205-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Ethics, ecology and development: Styles of ethics and styles of agriculture. [REVIEW]Charles V. Blatz - 1992 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 5 (1):59-85.
    This paper proposes to test the ethical acceptability of four styles of agricultural resource management: (1) contemporary industrial integrated systems agriculture, (2) modern industrial input dependent agriculture, (3) continuous traditional agriculture and (4) non-continuous (or swidden) traditional agriculture. The test of ethical acceptability is whether or not these styles of agricultural resource management embrace or are even compatible with that pattern of practical reasoning and interaction among ethical agents which we have independent theoretic grounds for preferring. The preferred sorts of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Facing Creation: When the Pragmatic Credo Masks the Orders of Action.Mathias Béjean & Armand Hatchuel - 2017 - Philosophy of Management 16 (3):197-210.
    This paper discusses the problematic use of the “pragmatic credo” – defined as a minimal set of basic pragmatist propositions – in practice, especially when facing creation. To do so, we analyze how managers deal with “art-based firms” and provide results from an in-depth case study of a small firm operating in garden art and design (Béjean 2015; 2008). The findings are interpreted in light of previous theoretical developments in management theory (Hatchuel European Management Review, 2(1): 36–47.), as well as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Could the stream of consciousness flow through the brain?Thomas Bittner - 2004 - Philosophia 31 (3-4):449-473.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Identities of Artefacts.Christoph Baumberger & Georg Brun - 2011 - Theoria 78 (1):47-74.
    In non-philosophical discourse, “identity” is often used when the specific character of artefacts is described or evaluated. We argue that this usage of “identity” can be explicated as referring to the symbol properties of artefacts as they are conceptualized in the symbol theory of Goodman and Elgin. This explication is backed by an analysis of various uses of “identity”. The explicandum clearly differs from the concepts of numerical identity, qualitative identity and essence, but it has a range of similarities with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bestialitatis and the New Ethics on “Human” Animals.Giuditta Bassano - 2018 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 31 (3):659-675.
    This article discusses how the legal systems in several Western countries, with a special focus on Italy, address our present day animal rights movement and how these legal systems can faithfully reflect the movement’s values as well as promote them in a manner that will ultimately change the rights themselves and their cultural context: this is an extremely interesting issue for the semiotic study of the “humanization of animals”. Therefore, I will summarize several semiotic arguments using the model of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Geometry to Conceptual Relativity.Thomas William Barrett & Hans Halvorson - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (5):1043-1063.
    The purported fact that geometric theories formulated in terms of points and geometric theories formulated in terms of lines are “equally correct” is often invoked in arguments for conceptual relativity, in particular by Putnam and Goodman. We discuss a few notions of equivalence between first-order theories, and we then demonstrate a precise sense in which this purported fact is true. We argue, however, that this fact does not undermine metaphysical realism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Consciousness is associated with central as well as distributed processes.Bernard J. Baars & Michael Fehling - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):203-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Throwing the conscious baby out with the Cartesian bath water.J. Aronson, E. Dietrich & E. Way - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):202-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The where and when of what?Michael V. Antony - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):201-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Bioethics and the challenges to its growth in Africa.Cletus T. Andoh - 2011 - Open Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):67.
    Bioethics has now become a burgeoning interdisciplinary field of scholarly investigation which has in the past decades migrated from bedside consultations to public policy debates and wider cultural and social consultations that privilege all discourse about everyday life issues. It has made exponential progress in addressing moral issues in science, technology and medicine in the world. In spite of this progress, core bioethics issues, approaches and values are still exclusively Western dominated and largely foreign to most African societies. Although medical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Why Designing Is Not Experimenting: Design Methods, Epistemic Praxis and Strategies of Knowledge Acquisition in Architecture.Sabine Ammon - 2017 - Philosophy and Technology 30 (4):495-520.
    Using the example of architecture, this article defends the thesis that designing should not be regarded as a kind of experimenting. This is in contrast to a widespread methodological claim that design processes are equivalent to experimentation processes. The contrary thesis can be proven by focusing on actual practices, techniques and design strategies. Closely connected with the thesis is an even more important epistemological claim, which contends that designing serves not only to develop artefacts but is also a means of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Scientific enquiry and natural kinds: from planets to mallards.P. D. Magnus - 2012 - New York, NY: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Some scientific categories seem to correspond to genuine features of the world and are indispensable for successful science in some domain; in short, they are natural kinds. This book gives a general account of what it is to be a natural kind and puts the account to work illuminating numerous specific examples.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations