Switch to: References

Citations of:

Ontogeny and Phylogeny

Science and Society 43 (1):104-106 (1979)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The search for an alternative to the sociobiological hypothesis.Peter J. Richerson & Robert T. Boyd - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):248-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • T. H. Huxley's Criticism of German Cell Theory: An Epigenetic and Physiological Interpretation of Cell Structure. [REVIEW]Marsha L. Richmond - 2000 - Journal of the History of Biology 33 (2):247 - 289.
    In 1853, the young Thomas Henry Huxley published a long review of German cell theory in which he roundly criticized the basic tenets of the Schleiden-Schwann model of the cell. Although historians of cytology have dismissed Huxley's criticism as based on an erroneous interpretation of cell physiology, the review is better understood as a contribution to embryology. "The Cell-theory" presents Huxley's "epigenetic" interpretation of histological organization emerging from changes in the protoplasm to replace the "preformationist" cell theory of Schleiden and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Ideology and the history of science.Robert J. Richards - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (1):103-108.
    discipline a general science of our "intellectual faculties, their principal phenomena, and the more remarkable circumstances of their activities" (1801, p. 4). Convinced of the sensationalist epistemology of Locke and Condillac, Destutt de Tracy believed one could resolve all ideas into the sensations that produced them and thereby test their soundness. The sensationalist assumptions of his project led him to propose that "ideology is a part of zoology" (1801, p. 1), and he consequently paid close attention to the way physiological..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ernst Haeckel’s Alleged Anti-Semitism and Contributions to Nazi Biology.Robert J. Richards - 2007 - Biological Theory 2 (1):97-103.
    Ernst Haeckel’s popular book Nat¨urliche Sch¨opfungs- geschichte (Natural history of creation, 1868) represents human species in a hierarchy, from lowest (Papuan and Hottentot) to highest (Caucasian, including the Indo-German and Semitic races). His stem-tree (see Figure 1) of human descent and the racial theories that accompany it have been the focus of several recent books—histories arguing that Haeckel had a unique position in the rise of Nazi biology during the first part of the 20th century. In 1971, Daniel Gasman brought (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Question of Properly Rights: Richard Owen's Evolutionism Reassessed.Evelleen Richards - 1987 - British Journal for the History of Science 20 (2):129-171.
    WhenVestiges of the Natural History of Creation, the anonymous evolutionary work which caused such a furore in mid-Victorian England, was published towards the close of 1844, Richard Owen, by then well-entrenched as the ‘British Cuvier’, received a complementary copy and addressed a letter to the author. This letter and how it should be interpreted have recently become the subject of historical debate, and this paper is directed at resolving the controversy. The question of Owen's attitude to theVestigesargument is central to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • From Sound to Music: An Evolutionary Approach to Musical Semantics. [REVIEW]Mark Reybrouck - 2013 - Biosemiotics 6 (3):1-22.
    This paper holds an evolutionary approach to musical semantics. Revolving around the nature/nurture dichotomy, it considers the role of the dispositional machinery to respond to sounding stimuli. Conceiving of music as organized sound, it stresses the dynamic tension between music as a collection of vibrational events and their potential of being structured. This structuring, however, is not gratuitous. It depends on levels of processing that rely on evolutionary older levels of reacting to the sounds as well as higher-level functions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Known general principles of learning cannot be ignored.Sam Revusky - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):156-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What about Sirenia?Bernhard Rensch - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):99-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The gain in the brain is plain when evo meets devo.Anton Reiner & Mario F. Wullimann - 2004 - Bioessays 26 (9):1026-1030.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pere Alberch: Originator of EvoDevo.John O. Reiss, Ann C. Burke, Charles Archer, Miquel De Renzi, Hernán Dopazo, Arantza Etxeberría, Emily A. Gale, J. Richard Hinchliffe, Laura Nuño de la Rosa Garcia, Chris S. Rose, Diego Rasskin-Gutman & Gerd B. Müller - 2008 - Biological Theory 3 (4):351-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructional morphology: The analysis of constraints in evolution dedicated to A. seilacher in honour of his 60. birthday.Wolf-Ernst Reify, Roger D. K. Thomas & Martin S. Fischer - 1985 - Acta Biotheoretica 34 (2-4):233-248.
    Evolutionary change is opportunistic, but its course is strongly constrained in several fundamental ways. These constraints (historical/phylogenetic, functional/adaptive, constructional/morphogenetic) and their dynamic relationships are discussed here and shown to constitute the conceptual framework of Constructional Morphology. Notwithstanding recent published opinions which claim that the discovery of constraints renders Neodarwinian selection theory obsolete, we regard the insights of Constructional Morphology as being entirely consistent with this theory. As is shown here in the case of the Hyracoidea, formal analysis of the constraints (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The “initial brain”: Initial considerations.Roger L. Reep - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):98-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Areas of ignorance and confusion in color science.Adam Reeves - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The civilizing process – According to Mennell, Elias and Freud.Harry Redner - 2015 - Thesis Eleven 127 (1):95-111.
    This article critiques theories of the civilizing process as expounded by its leading expositors: Mennell, Elias and Freud. It begins with a criticism of Stephen Mennell’s book The American Civilizing Process. This book relies on an even more famous work, Norbert Elias’s The Civilizing Process. Unfortunately, Mennell’s otherwise commendable attempt to capture American civilization in its historical scope and sociological complexity is misdirected because Eliasian theory is not applicable to America, as we will show, and, furthermore, offers a dubious account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Omitting the second person in social understanding.Vasudevi Reddy - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):140-141.
    Barresi & Moore do not consider information about intentional relations available within emotional engagement with others and do not see that others are perceived in the second as well as the third person. Recognising second person information forces recognition of similarities and connections not otherwise available. A developmental framework built on the assumption of the complete separateness of self and other is inevitably flawed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • An evolutionary context for the cognitive unconscious.Arthur S. Reber - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (1):33-51.
    This paper is an attempt to put the work of the past several decades on the problems of implicit learning and unconscious cognition into an evolutionary context. Implicit learning is an inductive process whereby knowledge of a complex environment is acquired and used largely independently of awareness of either the process of acquisition or the nature of that which has been learned. Characterized this way, implicit learning theory can be viewed as an attempt to come to grips with the classic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The Paradox of Isochrony in the Evolution of Human Rhythm.Andrea Ravignani & Guy Madison - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8:280885.
    Isochrony is crucial to the rhythm of human music. Some neural, behavioral and anatomical traits underlying rhythm perception and production are shared with a broad range of species. These may either have a common evolutionary origin, or have evolved into similar traits under different evolutionary pressures. Other traits underlying rhythm are rare across species, only found in humans and few other animals. Isochrony, or stable periodicity, is common to most human music, but isochronous behaviors are also found in many species. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The multiple directions of evolutionary change.Diego Rasskin-Gutman & Borja Esteve-Altava - 2008 - Bioessays 30 (6):521-525.
    The theory of Punctuated Equilibria challenges the neo‐Darwinian tenet that evolution is a uniform process. Recently, an article by Hunt1 has found that directional change during the evolution of a lineage is relatively small (occurring only in 5% of 250 analyzed traits). Of those traits that were shown to follow a trend, size was more likely to show gradual changes, whereas shape changes were more random. Here, we provide a short view of the nature of evolutionary trends, showing that directional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Primatologia, culturas não humanas e novas alteridades.Eliane Sebeika Rapchan & Walter Alves Neves - 2014 - Scientiae Studia 12 (2):309-329.
    De modo semelhante aos rompantes etnocêntricos de uma cultura humana frente a outras, as relações entre humanos e primatas não humanos incluem um estranhamento pontuado por atração e repulsa, identificação e diferença. Ciência, arte e mitologia são a expressão viva e atualizada disso. Desde 1960, a primatologia destaca-se nesse cenário por contribuir significativamente na revisão das definições sobre o comportamento dos primatas e, consequentemente, na redefinição do humano ao apresentar a polêmica proposição de existência de "culturas" entre animais não humanos. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Personal ads as deviant and unsatisfactory: Support for evolutionary hypotheses.D. W. Rajecki & Jeffrey Lee Rasmussen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):107-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Direct‐developing sea urchins and the evolutionary reorganization of early development.Rudolf A. Raff - 1992 - Bioessays 14 (4):211-218.
    The evolution of development can be made accessible to study by exploiting closely related species that exhibit distinct ontogenies. The direct‐developing sea urchin Heliocidaris erythrogramma is closely related to indirect‐developing sea urchins that develop via a feeding larval stage. Superficial consideration would suggest that simple heterochronies resulting in loss of larval features and acceleration of adult features could explain the substitution of direct for indirect development. However, our experiments show that early development has in fact been extensively remodeled, with modified (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Language, brain function, and human origins in the Victorian debates on evolution.Gregory Radick - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 31 (1):55-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Learning theory in its niche.Howard Rachlin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):155-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The molecular evolution of development.Michael D. Purugganan - 1998 - Bioessays 20 (9):700-711.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Culture and the evolution of learning.H. Ronald Pulliam - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):247-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contingency-governed science.Robert R. Provine - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):494-495.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ontogeny, form, function, and prediction.James C. Prechtl & Terry L. Powley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):318-331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentional schema will not do the work of a theory of mind.David Premack & Ann James Premack - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):138-140.
    Barresi & Moore's “intentional schema” will not do the work of “theory of mind.” Their model will account neither for fundamental facts of social competence, such as the social attributions of the 10-month-old infant, nor the possibility that, though having a theory of mind, the chimpanzee's theory is “weaker” than the human's.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • B-Afferents: A fundamental division of the nervous system mediating homeostasis?James C. Prechtl & Terry L. Powley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):289-300.
    The peripheral nervous system has classically been separated into a somatic division composed of both afferent and efferent pathways and an autonomic division containing only efferents. J. N. Langley, who codified this asymmetrical plan at the beginning of the twentieth century, considered different afferents, including visceral ones, as candidates for inclusion in his concept of the “autonomic nervous system”, but he finally excluded all candidates for lack of any distinguishing histological markers. Langley's classification has been enormously influential in shaping modern (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Goal directed behavior in the sensorimotor and language hierarchies.David M. W. Powers - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):572-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ontogeny, evolution, and folk psychology.Daniel J. Povinelli, Mia C. Zebouni & Christopher G. Prince - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):137-138.
    Barresi & Moore assume an equivalence between ontogenetic and evolutionaiy transformations of social understanding. The mechanisms of evolution allow for novel structures to arise, both through terminal addition and through the onset of novel pathways at time points that precede the end points of ancestral pathways. Terminal addition may not be the appropriate model for the evolution of human object-directed imitation, intermodal equivalence, or joint attention.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rethinking learning processes and products.Clotilde Pontecorvo - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):780-781.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Play—immediate or long-term adaptiveness?Frank E. Poirier - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):167-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neurobiology and linguistics are not yet unifiable.David Poeppel - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):642-643.
    Neurobiological models of language need a level of analysis that can account for the typical range of language phenomena. Because linguistically motivated models have been successful in explaining numerous language properties, it is premature to dismiss them as biologically irrelevant. Models attempting to unify neurobiology and linguistics need to be sensitive to both sources of evidence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Genes, mind, and emotion.Robert Plutchik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):21-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Possible mechanisms for a multiple-level model of evolution.H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):257-268.
    Many of the commentaries cohere around two major points of criticism. The first is that we have omitted discussion of the mechanisms that are assumed to operate at levels 2, 3, and 4.Campbell, Cloak, Dewsbury, Eckberg, Mundinger, Pulliam, Richerson & Boyd, Slobodkin, Simon, Williams, andWahlstenall make comments that bear on this point. The second point is that we have omitted discussion of the fact that "organisms change the environment by their activities" and thereby modify the selection pressures that act on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Linear and circular causal sequences.H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling-Smee - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):493-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is an ecological approach radical enough?H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling-Smee - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):154-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • A multiple-level model of evolution and its implications for sociobiology.H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling-Smee - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):225-235.
    The fundamental tenet of contemporary sociobiology, namely the assumption of a single process of evolution involving the selection of genes, is critically examined. An alternative multiple-level, multiple-process model of evolution is presented which posits that the primary process that operates via selection upon the genes cannot account for certain kinds of biological phenomena, especially complex, learned, social behaviours. The primary process has evolved subsidiary evolutionary levels and processes that act to bridge the gap between genes and these complex behaviours. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  • On the limits of quantitative genetics for the study of phenotypic evolution.Massimo Pigliucci & Carl D. Schlichting - 1997 - Acta Biotheoretica 45 (2):143-160.
    During the last two decades the role of quantitative genetics in evolutionary theory has expanded considerably. Quantitative genetic-based models addressing long term phenotypic evolution, evolution in multiple environments (phenotypic plasticity) and evolution of ontogenies (developmental trajectories) have been proposed. Yet, the mathematical foundations of quantitative genetics were laid with a very different set of problems in mind (mostly the prediction of short term responses to artificial selection), and at a time in which any details of the genetic machinery were virtually (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Pathogenesis: Freud’s Paul and the question of historical truth.Matthew J. Peterson - 2021 - Continental Philosophy Review 55 (1):35-53.
    This article retrieves Freud’s Paul as a forgotten predecessor and untapped critic of the “return to Paul” in contemporary political theology and continental philosophy. Given that Sigmund Freud published Moses and Monotheism in 1939 having barely escaped from Vienna, the text’s reception has justly been dominated by the question of Freud’s identification with Moses and the relationship between psychoanalysis and Judaism. However, I argue that this narrow focus has obscured the more fundamental problem of the connection between religion and Freud’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Linkage problems: Human genes and human culture.Steven A. Peterson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):247-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Immunoreactive theory: A conceptually narrow theory reflecting androcentric bias.Anne C. Petersen & Kathryn E. Hood - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):457-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A functional view of learning.Lewis Petrinovich - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):153-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three conceptions of explaining how possibly—and one reductive account.Johannes Persson - 2009 - In Henk W. de Regt (ed.), Epsa Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. Springer. pp. 275--286.
    Philosophers of science have often favoured reductive approaches to how-possibly explanation. This article identifies three alternative conceptions making how-possibly explanation an interesting phenomenon in its own right. The first variety approaches “how possibly X?” by showing that X is not epistemically impossible. This can sometimes be achieved by removing misunderstandings concerning the implications of one’s current belief system but involves characteristically a modification of this belief system so that acceptance of X does not result in contradiction. The second variety offers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Genetics, evolution and cultural selection.Anthony J. Perzigian - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):246-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tumourigenesis: The subterfuge of selection.Roy Douglas Pearson - 1981 - Acta Biotheoretica 30 (3):171-176.
    Variation or rearrangement of regulatory genes is responsible for cellular malignant change. These types of chromosomal variations also produce heterochrony or paedomorphic evolution at the organismal level. Analogously, neoplasia represents a cellular macroevolutionary event, and a tumour can be said to be an evolved population of cells. To understand this cellular evolution to malignancy, it may be necessary to go beyond a clonal selection (adaptationist) explanation of neoplastic alteration. In the pericellular environment natural selection consists of the organizational restraints of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neotenic blastemal morphogenesis.Roy Douglas Pearson - 1984 - Acta Biotheoretica 33 (1):51-59.
    Regeneration in arthropods and amphibians follows an analogous principle making comparisons between the two phyla possible.Larval arthropods and amphibians possess powers of epimorphic regeneration which wane for many species of these phyla with the completion of metamorphosis or the cessation of moulting. In those species which retain, post-maturationally, the ability to form a regenerative blastema, larval characteristics are carried into the adult and reproductive stages of these organisms. These include many species of: urodeles, ametabolous insects, crustaceans, myriapods and arachnids. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Amphibian regeneration and cellular heterochrony.Roy Douglas Pearson - 1982 - Acta Biotheoretica 31 (3):181-184.
    It is posited that the initiating event of amphibian regeneration of a limb, is retrodifferentiation* of what are to become the developing cells of the blastema. These cells reiterate a larval or premetamorphic ontogenic repertoire, induced by elevated levels of prolactin with adequate innervation. Subsequent redifferentiation of the blastema cells occurs, controlled by thyroxine and innervation.This temporal displacement of cellular morphologic characters in regeneration should be looked upon as a function of the ability to reiterate larval characters and subsequently metamorphose. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Senescence, Growth, and Gerontology in the United States.Hyung Wook Park - 2013 - Journal of the History of Biology 46 (4):631-667.
    This paper discusses how growth and aging became interrelated phenomena with the creation of gerontology in the United States. I first show that the relation of growth to senescence, which had hardly attracted scientific attention before the twentieth century, started to be investigated by several experimental scientists around the 1900s. Subsequently, research on the connection between the two phenomena entered a new domain through the birth of gerontology as a scientific field comprised of various disciplines, many of which addressed growth. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark