Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Discovery and explanation in sociology: Durkheim on suicide.Toby E. Huff - 1975 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 5 (2):241-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Discovery and Explanation in Sociology: Durkheim on Suicide.Toby E. Huff - 1975 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 5 (3):241-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Zuriff on observability.Max Hocutt - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):706-707.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Repressed infantile wishes as the instigators of all dreams.J. Allan Hobson - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):241-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rebuilding behaviorism: Too many relatives on the construction site?Philip N. Hineline - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):706-706.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Duhem, Quine and a New Empiricism.Mary Hesse - 1969 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 3:191-209.
    As in the case of great books in all branches of philosophy, Pierre Duhem's Le Théorie Physique , first published in 1906, can be looked to as the progenitor of many different and even conflicting currents in subsequent philosophy of science. On a superficial reading, it seems to be an expression of what later came to be called deductivist and instrumentalist analyses of scientific theory. Duhem's very definition of physical theory, put forward early in the book, is the quintessence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Duhem, Quine and a New Empiricism.Mary Hesse - 1969 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 3:191-209.
    As in the case of great books in all branches of philosophy, Pierre Duhem's Le Théorie Physique, first published in 1906, can be looked to as the progenitor of many different and even conflicting currents in subsequent philosophy of science. On a superficial reading, it seems to be an expression of what later came to be called deductivist and instrumentalist analyses of scientific theory. Duhem's very definition of physical theory, put forward early in the book, is the quintessence of instrumentalism:A (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Computation, cognition, and representation.John Hell - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):139-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology and computational architecture.John Haugeland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human and computer rules and representations are not equivalent.Stephen Grossberg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):136-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Do Disputes over Priority Tell Us Anything about Science?Alan G. Gross - 1998 - Science in Context 11 (2):161-179.
    The ArgumentConflicts between scientists over credit for their discoveries are conflicts, not merely in, but of science because discovery is not a historical event, but a retrospective social judgment. There is no objective moment of discovery; rather, discovery is established by means of a hermeneutics, a way of reading scientific articles. The priority conflict between Roger Guillemin and Andrew Schally over the discovery of the brain hormone, TRF, serves as an example. The work of Robert Merton, Thomas Kuhn, Augustine Brannigan, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Précis of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique.Adolf Grünbaum - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):217-228.
    This book critically examines Freud's own detailed arguments for his major explanatory and therapeutic principles, the current neorevisionist versions of psychoanalysis, and the hermeneuticists' reconstruction of Freud's theory and therapy as an alternative to what they claim was a “scientistic” misconstrual of the psychoanalytic enterprise. The clinical case for Freud's cornerstone theory of repression – the claim that psychic conflict plays a causal role in producing neuroses, dreams, and bungled actions – turns out to be ill-founded for two main reasons: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Unnatural epistemology.John D. Greenwood - 2007 - Mind and Language 22 (2):132-149.
    ‘Naturalized’ philosophers of mind regularly appeal to the empirical psychological literature in support of the ‘theory-theory’ account of the natural epistemology of mental state ascription (to self and others). It is argued that such appeals are not philosophically neutral, but in fact presuppose the theory-theory account of mental state ascription. It is suggested that a possible explanation of the popularity of the theory-theory account is that it is generally assumed that alternative accounts in terms of introspection (and simulation) presuppose a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two dogmas of neo-empiricism: The "theory-informity" of observation and the Quine-Duhem thesis.John D. Greenwood - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (4):553-574.
    It is argued that neither the "theory-informity" of observations nor the Quine-Duhem thesis pose any in principle threat to the objectivity of theory evaluation. The employment of exploratory theories does not generate incommensurability, but on the contrary is responsible for the mensurability and commensurability of explanatory theories, since exploratory theories enable scientists to make observations which are critical in the evaluation of explanatory theories. The employment of exploratory theories and other auxiliary hypotheses does not enable a theory to always accommodate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Scientific psychology and hermeneutical psychology: Causal explanation and the meaning of human action. [REVIEW]John D. Greenwood - 1987 - Human Studies 10 (2):171 - 204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sunyata in the West.David Grandy - unknown
    I argue that sunyata, or something like it, manifested itself in early Western thought. While Plato and Aristotle resisted emptiness or nothingness, they nevertheless felt themselves obliged to venture close to its edge in order to ground their explanations of changing reality to unchanging principles. These principles embody much of the indeterminancy long associated with the Mahayana understanding of sunyata. Although their function was to enable lasting explanations of reality by putting change out of play, they themselves shade off toward (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • First-person behaviorism.George Graham - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):704-705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Moral Innocence as Illusion and Inability.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2015 - Philosophia 43 (2):355-366.
    The concept of moral innocence is frequently referenced in popular culture, ordinary language, literature, religious doctrine, and psychology. The morally innocent are often thought to be morally pure, incapable of wrongdoing, ignorant of morality, resistant to sin, or even saintly. In spite of, or perhaps because of this frequency of use the characterization of moral innocence continues to have varying connotations. As a result, the concept is often used without sufficient heed given to some of its most salient attributes, especially (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Complementing explanation with induction.Clark Glymour - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):655-656.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Looking angry and sounding sad: The perceptual analysis of emotional expression.Trip Glazer - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3619-3643.
    According to the Perceptual Analysis of Emotional Expression, behaviors express emotions by making them perceptually manifest. A smile is an expression of joy because an observer who sees a smile can see joy. A pout is an expression of grief because an observer who sees a pout can see grief. And a growl is an expression of anger because an observer who hears a growl can hear anger. The idea is not simply that expressions can enable the perception of emotion, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Dynamical Phenomena and Their Models: Truth and Empirical Correctness.Marco Giunti - 2023 - Foundations of Science 28 (1):327-375.
    In the epistemological tradition, there are two main interpretations of the semantic relation that an empirical theory may bear to the real world. According to realism, the theory-world relationship should be conceived as truth; according to instrumentalism, instead, it should be limited to empirical adequacy. Then, depending on how empirical theories are conceived, either syntactically as a class of sentences, or semantically as a class of models, the concepts of truth and empirical adequacy assume different and specific forms. In this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are micro-entities picturable?T. R. Girill - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (4):570-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From tools to theories: A heuristic of discovery in cognitive psychology.Gerd Gigerenzer - 1991 - Psychological Review 98 (2):254-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • Discovery in Cognitive Psychology: New Tools Inspire New Theories.Gerd Gigerenzer - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (2):329-350.
    The ArgumentScientific tools—measurement and calculation instruments, techniques of inference—straddle the line between the context of discovery and the context of justification. In discovery, new scientific tools suggest new theoretical metaphors and concepts; and in justification, these tool-derived theoretical metaphors and concepts are morelikely to be accepted by the scientific community if the tools are already entrenched in scientific practice.Techniques of statistical inference and hypothesis testing entered American psychology first as tools in the 1940s and 1950s and then as cognitive theories (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Misreporting rules.Dan S. Felsenthal & Moshé Machover - unknown
    In the voting-power literature the rules of decision of the US Congress and the UN Security Council are widely misreported as though abstention amounts to a `no' vote. The hypothesis (proposed elsewhere) that this is due to a specific cause, theory-laden observation, is tested here by examining accounts of these rules in introductory textbooks on American Government and International Relations, where that putative cause does not apply. Our examination does not lead to a conclusive outcome regarding the hypothesis, but reveals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reassessing Discovery: Rosalind Franklin, Scientific Visualization, and the Structure of DNA.Michelle G. Gibbons - 2012 - Philosophy of Science 79 (1):63-80.
    Philosophers have traditionally conceived of discovery in terms of internal cognitive acts. Close consideration of Rosalind Franklin's role in the discovery of the DNA double helix, however, reveals some problems with this traditional conception. This article argues that defining discovery in terms of mental operations entails problematic conclusions and excludes acts that should fall within the domain of discovery. It proposes that discovery be expanded to include external acts of making visible. Doing so allows for a reevaluation of Franklin's role (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Argumentation and learning.Baruch B. Schwarz - 2009 - In Nathalie Muller Mirza & Anne Nelly Perret-Clermont (eds.), Argumentation and education. New York: Springer. pp. 91--126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Metaphor and Thinking in Science and Religion.Mary Gerhart & Allan Melvin Russell - 2004 - Zygon 39 (1):13-38.
    Excerpts from Chapters 1 and 3 of New Maps for Old: Explorations in Science and Religion (Gerhart and Russell 2001) explore the ramifications of metaphoric process for changes in thinking, especially those changes that lead to a new understanding of our world. Examples are provided from science, from religion, and from science and religion together. In excerpts from Chapter 8, a double analogy—theology is to science as science is to mathematics—is proposed for better understanding the contemporary relationship between science and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Experience and Theory.Mary Gerhart & Allan Melvin Russell - 2004 - Zygon 39 (1):5-11.
    Excerpts from Chapters 1 and 3 of New Maps for Old: Explorations in Science and Religion (Gerhart and Russell 2001) explore the ramifications of metaphoric process for changes in thinking, especially those changes that lead to a new understanding of our world. Examples are provided from science, from religion, and from science and religion together. In excerpts from Chapter 8, a double analogy—theology is to science as science is to mathematics—is proposed for better understanding the contemporary relationship between science and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strategies of inquiry : The ‘Sherlock Holmes sense of deduction’ revisited.Emmanuel J. Genot - 2018 - Synthese 195 (5):2065-2088.
    This paper examines critically the reconstruction of the ‘Sherlock Holmes sense of deduction’ proposed jointly by M.B. Hintikka and J. Hintikka in the 1980s, and its successor, the interrogative model of inquiry developed by J. Hintikka and his collaborators in the 1990s. The Hintikkas’ model explicitly used game theory in order to formalize a naturalistic approach to inquiry, but the imi abandoned both the game-theoretic formalism, and the naturalistic approach. It is argued that the latter better supports the claim that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Warranting interpretations.Alan Gauld & John Shotter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):239-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Understanding the Nature of Science Through a Critical and Reflective Analysis of the Controversy Between Pasteur and Liebig on Fermentation.Antonio García-Carmona & José Antonio Acevedo-Díaz - 2017 - Science & Education 26 (1-2):65-91.
    This article presents a qualitative study, descriptive-interpretive in profile, of the effectiveness in learning about the nature of science of an activity relating to the historical controversy between Pasteur and Liebig on fermentation. The activity was implemented during a course for pre-service secondary science teachers specializing in physics and chemistry. The approach was explicit and reflective. Three research questions were posed: What conceptions of NOS do the PSSTs show after a first reflective reading of the historical controversy?, What role is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kuhn and the quantum controversy. [REVIEW]Peter Galison - 1981 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (1):71-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kordig and the theory-ladenness of observation.George Gale & Edward Walter - 1973 - Philosophy of Science 40 (3):415-432.
    In a series of articles, the most extensive of which are [9] and [10], Carl R. Kordig has attacked the "new empiricism" of the late Norwood R. Hanson, P. K. Feyerabend, Thomas S. Kuhn, and Stephen E. Toulmin. While there are differ- ences among the views of these philosophers, they agree at least on the following claims: (1) scientific method does not proceed inductively from neutral observations because (a) observations are not free of interpretation; and (b) scientists, as a matter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Descubrimiento, justificación e inferencia a la mejor explicación.Rodolfo Gaeta - 2008 - Principia 12 (2):193-202.
    http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2008v12n2p193 In this paper I claim that the bias to pass from the acknowledgement of the explanatory virtues of a hypothesis to the belief that it is true or approximate to the truth is so strong that scientific realists can hardly elude that temptation. For that reason, some philosophers, like McMullin and Okasha, following Peirce and Hanson, participate of the conviction that the skill of founding scientific explanations bears the ability of founding true theories. But, this way, they pass the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Genealogy of Judgement: Towards a Deep History of Academic Freedom.Steve Fuller - 2009 - British Journal of Educational Studies 57 (2):164-177.
    The classical conception of academic freedom associated with Wilhelm von Humboldt and the rise of the modern university has a quite specific cultural foundation that centres on the controversial mental faculty of 'judgement'. This article traces the roots of 'judgement' back to the Protestant Reformation, through its heyday as the signature feature of German idealism, and to its gradual loss of salience as both a philosophical and a psychological concept. This trajectory has been accompanied by a general shrinking in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rorty Reframed.Steve Fuller - 2023 - Common Knowledge 29 (1):86-101.
    Richard Rorty is easily cast as the intellectual godfather of our post-truth condition. But unlike Nicholas Gaskill, whose article in Common Knowledge 28, no. 3, has engendered a continuing symposium in the journal, Professor Fuller sees Rorty's role as being to his credit rather than detriment. Rorty extended W. B. Gallie's idea of “essentially contested concepts” from the moral and political spheres to the epistemic, thereby rendering such terms as truth, reason, and evidence inherently vague, which means that they are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paving the Way for an Evolutionary Social Constructivism.Andreas De Block & Bart Du Laing - 2007 - Biological Theory 2 (4):337-348.
    The idea has recently taken root that evolutionary theory and social constructivism are less antagonistic than most theorists thought, and we have even seen attempts at integrating constructivist and evolutionary approaches to human thought and behaviour. We argue in this article that although the projected integration is possible, indeed valuable, the existing attempts have tended to be vague or overly simplistic about the claims of social constructivist. We proceed by examining how to give more precision and substance to the research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the Theory Dependance of Observation.Martin Frické - 1983 - Philosophica 31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Educational Research and Two Traditions of Epistemology.Helen Freeman & Alison Jones - 1980 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 12 (2):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Matthew Freund, Verle E. Headings, Angela Belli, Gregory E. Pence, Howard Brody, Leonard M. Fleck, Charles Perakis & James A. Knight - 1987 - Journal of Medical Humanities and Bioethics 8 (2):141-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is theory gendered?Elizabeth Frazer - 1996 - Journal of Political Philosophy 4 (2):169–189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defence of the armchair.Michael Fortescue - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):135-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychoanalysis as a social activity.Owen J. Flanagan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):238-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sequence Data, Phylogenetic Inference, and Implications of Downward Causation.Kirk Fitzhugh - 2016 - Acta Biotheoretica 64 (2):133-160.
    Framing systematics as a field consistent with scientific inquiry entails that inferences of phylogenetic hypotheses have the goal of producing accounts of past causal events that explain differentially shared characters among organisms. Linking observations of characters to inferences occurs by way of why-questions implied by data matrices. Because of their form, why-questions require the use of common-cause theories. Such theories in phylogenetic inferences include natural selection and genetic drift. Selection or drift can explain ‘morphological’ characters but selection cannot be causally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Mental models in data interpretation.Clark A. Chinn & William F. Brewer - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):219.
    This paper presents a cognitive account of the process of evaluating scientific data. Our account assumes that when individuals evaluate data, they construct a mental model of a data-interpretation package, in which the data and theoretical interpretations of the data are integrated. We propose that individuals attempt to discount data by seeking alternative explanations for events within the mental model; data-interpretation packages are accepted when the individual cannot find alternative accounts for these events. Our analysis indicates that there are many (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific discovery and Maxwell's kinetic theory.Peter Achinstein - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (3):409-434.
    By reference to Maxwell's kinetic theory, one feature of hypothetico-deductivism is defended. A scientist need make no inference to a hypothesis when he first proposes it. He may have no reason at all for thinking it is true. Yet it may be worth considering. In developing his kinetic theory there were central assumptions Maxwell made (for example, that molecules are spherical, that they exert contact forces, and that their motion is linear) that he had no reason to believe true. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Grünbaum on Freud: Three grounds for dissent.Arthur Fine & Micky Forbes - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):237-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The probative value of the clinical data of psychoanalysis.B. A. Farrell - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):236-237.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a More Effective Thick Description: A Biosemiotic Approach to Meaning in Psychotherapy.Annibale Fanali, Francesco Tramonti & Franco Giorgi - 2022 - Biosemiotics 15 (3):519-530.
    Thick description was originally proposed to overcome the limitations of quantitative research and ground anthropological observations in concrete people’s expectations, rather than in normative theories. The ultimate objective was to account for the emotional aspects of worldviews and value-orientations that would otherwise be left tacit or implicit by quantitative investigations. The present paper aimed at reviewing the _conceptual framework_ that has characterized this relational turn and has made possible a deeper understanding of the subjective experience. The primary objective is thus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark