Switch to: References

Citations of:

Knowledge and belief

Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press (1962)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Suppose Yalcin is wrong about epistemic modals.Joshua D. Crabill - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 162 (3):625-635.
    In “Epistemic Modals,” Seth Yalcin argues that what explains the deficiency of sentences containing epistemic modals of the form ‘p and it might be that not-p’ is that sentences of this sort are strictly contradictory, and thus are not instances of a Moore-paradox as has been previous suggested. Benjamin Schnieder, however, argues in his Yalcin’s explanation of these sentences’ deficiency turns out to be insufficiently general, as it cannot account for less complex but still defective sentences, such as ‘Suppose it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Strategies for securing evidence through model criticism.Kent W. Staley - 2012 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (1):21-43.
    Some accounts of evidence regard it as an objective relationship holding between data and hypotheses, perhaps mediated by a testing procedure. Mayo’s error-statistical theory of evidence is an example of such an approach. Such a view leaves open the question of when an epistemic agent is justified in drawing an inference from such data to a hypothesis. Using Mayo’s account as an illustration, I propose a framework for addressing the justification question via a relativized notion, which I designate security , (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • New Essays on the Knowability Paradox – Edited by Joe Salerno.Hans Van Ditmarsch - 2010 - Theoria 76 (3):270-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A logic of explicit knowledge.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    A well-known problem with Hintikka-style logics of knowledge is that of logical omniscience. One knows too much. This breaks down into two subproblems: one knows all tautologies, and one’s knowledge is closed under consequence. A way of addressing the second of these is to move from knowledge simpliciter, to knowledge for a reason. Then, as consequences become ‘further away’ from one’s basic knowledge, reasons for them become more complex, thus providing a kind of resource measurement. One kind of reason is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Quantified Hintikka-style epistemic logic.Lauri Carlson - 1988 - Synthese 74 (2):223 - 262.
    This paper contains a formal treatment of the system of quantified epistemic logic sketched in Appendix II of Carlson (1983). Section 1 defines the syntax and recapitulates the model set rules and principles of the Appendix system. Section 2 defines a possible worlds semantics for this system, and shows that the Appendix system is complete with respect to this semantics. Section 3 extends the system by an explicit truth operatorT it is true that and considers quantification over nonexistent individuals. Section (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Intention, cognitive commitment, and planning.Robert Audi - 1991 - Synthese 86 (3):361-378.
    This paper defends a cognitive-motivational account of intending against recent criticism by J. Garcia, connects intending with a number of other concepts important in the theory of action — including decison, volition, and planning — and explores some principles of intention transfer construed as counterparts of epistemic principles governing closure for belief and justification. Several routes to intention formation are described; the role of intentions in planning is examined; and a holistic conception of intention formation and change is stressed. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Theory of Questions, Epistemic Powers, and the Indexical Theory of Knowledge.Hector-Neri Castañeda - 1980 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1):193-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • In Support of the Weak Rhetoric as Epistemic Thesis. On the Generality and Reliability of Persuasion Knowledge.Frank Zenker - 2013 - In Belle van, P. Gillaerts, B. van Gorp, D. van de Mieroop & K. Rutten (eds.), Verbal and Visual Rhetoric in a Media World. pp. 61-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conditionally Knowing What.Yanjing Wang & Jie Fan - 2014 - In Rajeev Goré, Barteld Kooi & Agi Kurucz (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Volume 10: Papers From the Tenth Aiml Conference, Held in Groningen, the Netherlands, August 2014. London, England: CSLI Publications. pp. 569-587.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Public and private communication are different: results on relative expressivity.Bryan Renne - 2008 - Synthese 165 (2):225-245.
    Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL) is the study of how to reason about knowledge, belief, and communication. This paper studies the relative expressivity of certain fragments of the DEL language for public and private communication. It is shown that the language of public communication with common knowledge and the language of private communication with common knowledge are expressively incomparable for the class of all pointed Kripke models, which provides a formal proof that public and private communication are fundamentally different in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ockham’s razor and reasoning about information flow.Mehrnoosh Sadrzadeh - 2009 - Synthese 167 (2):391-408.
    What is the minimal algebraic structure to reason about information flow? Do we really need the full power of Boolean algebras with co-closure and de Morgan dual operators? How much can we weaken and still be able to reason about multi-agent scenarios in a tidy compositional way? This paper provides some answers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Jaakko Hintikka in memoriam.Gabriel Sandu - 2015 - Theoria 81 (4):289-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Interpretace znalosti v substrukturálních rámcích.Ondrej Majer & Michal Peliš - 2013 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 20 (1):79-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantics for Knowledge and Change of Awareness.Hans van Ditmarsch & Tim French - 2014 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 23 (2):169-195.
    We examine various logics that combine knowledge, awareness, and change of awareness. An agent can become aware of propositional propositions but also of other agents or of herself. The dual operation to becoming aware, forgetting, can also be modelled. Our proposals are based on a novel notion of structural similarity that we call awareness bisimulation, the obvious notion of modal similarity for structures encoding knowledge and awareness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On interpreting “interpretive use”.N. V. Smith - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):734.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reasoning About Games.Melvin Fitting - 2011 - Studia Logica 99 (1-3):143-169.
    is used to give a formalization of Artemov’s knowledge based reasoning approach to game theory, (KBR), [ 4 , 5 ]. Epistemic states of players are represented explicitly and reasoned about formally. We give a detailed analysis of the Centipede game using both proof theoretic and semantic machinery. This helps make the case that PDL + E can be a useful basis for the logical investigation of game theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Inconsistencies in extensive games.Martin Dufwenberg & Johan Lindén - 1996 - Erkenntnis 45 (1):103 - 114.
    In certain finite extensive games with perfect information, Cristina Bicchieri (1989) derives a logical contradiction from the assumptions that players are rational and that they have common knowledge of the theory of the game. She argues that this may account for play outside the Nash equilibrium. She also claims that no inconsistency arises if the players have the minimal beliefs necessary to perform backward induction. We here show that another contradiction can be derived even with minimal beliefs, so there is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Knowledge condition games.Sieuwert van Otterloo, Wiebe Van Der Hoek & Michael Wooldridge - 2006 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 15 (4):425-452.
    Understanding the flow of knowledge in multi-agent protocols is essential when proving the correctness or security of such protocols. Current logical approaches, often based on model checking, are well suited for modeling knowledge in systems where agents do not act strategically. Things become more complicated in strategic settings. In this paper we show that such situations can be understood as a special type of game – a knowledge condition game – in which a coalition “wins” if it is able to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Display calculi for logics with relative accessibility relations.Stéphane Demri & Rajeev Goré - 2000 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 9 (2):213-236.
    We define cut-free display calculi for knowledge logics wherean indiscernibility relation is associated to each set of agents, andwhere agents decide the membership of objects using thisindiscernibility relation. To do so, we first translate the knowledgelogics into polymodal logics axiomatised by primitive axioms and thenuse Kracht's results on properly displayable logics to define thedisplay calculi. Apart from these technical results, we argue thatDisplay Logic is a natural framework to define cut-free calculi for manyother logics with relative accessibility relations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Essay Review.M. Detlefsen - 1988 - History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (1):93-105.
    S. SHAPIRO (ed.), Intensional Mathematics (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 11 3). Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1985. v + 230 pp. $38.50/100Df.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A representational account of mutual belief.Robert C. Koons - 1989 - Synthese 81 (1):21 - 45.
    Although the notion of common or mutual belief plays a crucial role in game theory, economics and social philosophy, no thoroughly representational account of it has yet been developed. In this paper, I propose two desiderata for such an account, namely, that it take into account the possibility of inconsistent data without portraying the human mind as logically and mathematically omniscient. I then propose a definition of mutual belief which meets these criteria. This account takes seriously the existence of computational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Category mistakes in m&e.Gilbert Harman - 2003 - Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1):165–180.
    Theories of causation may imply that your birth causes your death, which seems odd in the way that it is not odd to say that your birth precedes your death. Theories of knowledge may imply that the object of knowledge is the same as the object of belief, although we know but do not believe facts and we can know a proposition without knowing whether it is true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Antinomies and paradoxes and their solutions.Paul Weingartner - 1990 - Studies in Soviet Thought 39 (3-4):313-331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Glauben, Wissen und Wahrscheinlichkeit. Systeme der epistemischen Logik.Kazem Sadegh-Zadeh - 1982 - Metamedicine 3 (2):297-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Foundations of clinical praxiology part II: Categorical and conjectural diagnoses.Kazem Sadegh-Zadeh - 1982 - Metamedicine 3 (1):101-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Freedom and Enforcement in Action: A Study in Formal Action Theory.Janusz Czelakowski - 2015 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Situational aspects of action are discussed. The presented approach emphasizes the role of situational contexts in which actions are performed. These contexts influence the course of an action; they are determined not only by the current state of the system but also shaped by other factors as time, the previously undertaken actions and their succession, the agents of actions and so on. The distinction between states and situations is explored from the perspective of action systems. The notion of a situational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A “questão da existência” no Poema de Parmênides.José Gabriel Trindade Santos - 2012 - Filosofia Unisinos 13 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On a Neg‐Raising Fallacy in Determining Enthymematicity: If She Did not Believe or Want ….Katarzyna Paprzycka - 2014 - Metaphilosophy 45 (1):96-119.
    Many arguments that show p to be enthymematic (in an argument for q) rely on claims like “if one did not believe that p, one would not have a reason for believing that q.” Such arguments are susceptible to the neg-raising fallacy. We tend to interpret claims like “X does not believe that p” as statements of disbelief (X's belief that not-p) rather than as statements of withholding the belief that p. This article argues that there is a tendency to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Actions on belief.Sam Steel - 1994 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 4 (1):29-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Awareness and equilibrium.Brian Hill - 2013 - Synthese 190 (5):851-869.
    There has been a recent surge of interest among economists in developing models of doxastic states that can account for some aspects of human cognitive limitations that are ignored by standard formal models, such as awareness. Epistemologists purport to have a principled reason for ignoring the question of awareness: under the equilibrium conception of doxastic states they favour, a doxastic state comprises the doxastic commitments an agent would recognise were he fully aware, so the question of awareness plays no role. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Must we quantify into opaque contexts?Michael Byrd - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 26 (5-6):401 - 409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Problems with persistence.Nicholas Asher - 1994 - Topoi 13 (1):37-49.
    A fundamental question in reasoning about change is, what information does a reasoning agent infer about later times from earlier times? I will argue that reasoning about change by an agent is to be modeled in terms of the persistence of the agent''s beliefs over time rather than the persistence of truth and that such persistence is explained by pragmatic factors about how agents acquire information from other agents rather than by general principles of persistence about states of the world. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Duty and knowledge.Yoaav Isaacs - 2014 - Philosophical Perspectives 28 (1):95-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Charity Implies Meta‐Charity.Roy Sorensen - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (2):290-315.
    The principle of charity says that all agents are rational. The principle of meta‐charity says that all agents believe all agents are rational. My thesis is that the arguments which are used to support charity also support meta‐charity. Meta‐charity implies meta‐meta‐charity. By recursion, the principle of charity implies that it is common knowledge. But there appears to be intelligent, well‐informed disagreement with the principle of charity. So if the entailment thesis holds, opponents of the principle of charity have a new (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Generation and Selection of Abductive Explanations for Non-Omniscient Agents.Fernando Soler-Toscano & Fernando R. Velázquez-Quesada - 2014 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 23 (2):141-168.
    Among the non-monotonic reasoning processes, abduction is one of the most important. Usually described as the process of looking for explanations, it has been recognized as one of the most commonly used in our daily activities. Still, the traditional definitions of an abductive problem and an abductive solution mention only theories and formulas, leaving agency out of the picture. Our work proposes a study of abductive reasoning from an epistemic and dynamic perspective. In the first part we explore syntactic definitions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Invitation to Autoepistemology.Lloyd Humberstone - 2002 - Theoria 68 (1):13-51.
    The phrase ‘autoepistemic logic’ was introduced in Moore [1985] to refer to a study inspired in large part by criticisms in Stalnaker [1980] of a particular nonmonotonic logic proposed by McDermott and Doyle.1 Very informative discussions for those who have not encountered this area are provided by Moore [1988] and the wide-ranging survey article Konolige [1994], and the scant remarks in the present introductory section do not pretend to serve in place of those treatments as summaries of the field. A (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How an agent might think.A. Szalas - 2013 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 21 (3):515-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What will they say?—Public Announcement Games.Hans van Ditmarsch & Thomas Ågotnes - 2011 - Synthese 179 (S1):57 - 85.
    Dynamic epistemic logic describes the possible information-changing actions available to individual agents, and their knowledge pre-and post conditions. For example, public announcement logic describes actions in the form of public, truthful announcements. However, little research so far has considered describing and analysing rational choice between such actions, i.e., predicting what rational self-interested agents actually will or should do. Since the outcome of information exchange ultimately depends on the actions chosen by all the agents in the system, and assuming that agents (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Implicit Versus Explicit Knowledge in Dialogical Logic.Manuel Rebuschi - 2009 - In Ondrej Majer, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Tero Tulenheimo (eds.), Games: Unifying Logic, Language, and Philosophy. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag. pp. 229--246.
    A dialogical version of (modal) epistemic logic is outlined, with an intuitionistic variant. Another version of dialogical epistemic logic is then provided by means of the S4 mapping of intuitionistic logic. Both systems cast new light on the relationship between intuitionism, modal logic and dialogical games.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conditions of Rationality for Scientific Research.Paul Weingartner - 2019 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 33 (2):67-118.
    The purpose of this paper is to discuss conditions of rationality for scientific research (SR) where "conditions" are understood as "necessary conditions". This will be done in the following way: First, I shall deal with the aim of SR since conditions of rationality (for SR) are to be understood as necessary means for reaching the aim (goal) of SR. Subsequently, the following necessary conditions will be discussed: Rational Communication, Methodological Rules, Ideals of Rationality and its Realistic Aspects, Methodological and Ontological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Hooded Man.Priest Graham - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (5):445-467.
    The Hooded Man Paradox of Eubulides concerns the apparent failure of the substitutivity of identicals in epistemic (and other intentional) contexts. This paper formulates a number of different versions of the paradox and shows how these may be solved using semantics for quantified epistemic logic. In particular, two semantics are given which invalidate substitution, even when rigid designators are involved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Uniform and non uniform strategies for tableaux calculi for modal logics.Stéphane Demri - 1995 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 5 (1):77-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Two-dimensional awareness logics.Hu Liu & Shier Ju - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (5):481-495.
    Awareness logic is a type of belief logic in which an agent's beliefs are restricted to those sentences that the agent is aware of. Awareness logic is a successful way to circumvent the problem of omniscience so that actual belief is modelled in a reasonable way. In this paper, we suggest a new method modelling awareness and actual belief by using two-dimensional logics. We show that the two-dimensional logics are flexible tools. Different types of concepts of awareness can be easily (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Landscape of Logics beyond the Deduction Theorem.Bas C. van Fraassen - 2022 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 26 (1):25-38.
    Philosophical issues often turn into logic. That is certainly true of Moore’s Paradox, which tends to appear and reappear in many philosophical contexts. There is no doubt that its study belongs to pragmatics rather than semantics or syntax. But it is also true that issues in pragmatics can often be studied fruitfully by attending to their projection, so to speak, onto the levels of semantics or syntax — just in the way that problems in spherical geometry are often illuminated by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inference and update.Fernando Raymundo Velázquez-Quesada - 2009 - Synthese 169 (2):283-300.
    We look at two fundamental logical processes, often intertwined in planning and problem solving: inference and update. Inference is an internal process with which we uncover what is implicit in the information we already have. Update, on the other hand, is produced by external communication, usually in the form of announcements and in general in the form of observations, giving us information that might not have been available (even implicitly) before. Both processes have received attention from the logic community, usually (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Informativeness and Moore's Paradox.Peter Pagin - 2008 - Analysis 68 (1):46-57.
    The first case is usually referred to as omissive and the second as commissive. What is traditionally perceived as paradoxical is that although such statements may well be true, asserting them is clearly absurd. An account of Moore’s Paradox is an explanation of the absurdity. In the last twenty years, there has also been a focus on the incoherence of judging or believing such propositions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Some Limitations to the Psychological Orientation in Semantic Theory.Richmond H. Thomason - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (1):1 - 14.
    The psychological orientation treats semantics as a matter of idealized computation over symbolic structures, and semantic relations like denotation as relations between linguistic expressions and these structures. I argue that results similar to Gödel's incompleteness theorems and Tarski's theorem on truth create foundational difficulties for this view of semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Theory of Knowledge Based on the Idea of the Discursive Space.Rafal Maciag - 2022 - Philosophies 7 (4):72.
    This paper discusses the theory of knowledge based on the idea of dynamical space. The goal of this effort is to comprehend the knowledge that remains beyond the human domain, e.g., of the artificial cognitive systems. This theory occurs in two versions, weak and strong. The weak version is limited to knowledge in which retention and articulation are performed through the discourse. The strong version is general and is not limited in any way. In the weak version, knowledge is represented (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • L’interaction sociale comme fondement de la signification logique.Adjoua Bernadette Dango - 2017 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 9:121-142.
    Our article aims to show, on the one hand, the preeminence of the interactive paradigm as a determining element in the process of constitution of logical meaning and, on the other hand, to examine the contents of the linguistic expressions of pragmatic semantics. To do this, we expose three major figures of the logic of mathematical obedience in particular those of Gottfreid Leibniz, George Boole and Gottlob Frege. If this approach to mathematical logic has seen meritorious progress, it should be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zur Methodologie von Kombinationstests in der analytischen Philosophie.Hans-Ulrich Hoche - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):28-54.
    Summary Ordinary language philosophers frequently draw on the fact that an appropriately selected sentential combination of the form p but not q can, or cannot, be uttered without absurdity; however, they do so without sufficient reflection on the methodology of such combination tests, which results in considerable shortcomings even in practical application. To improve things, I shall discuss two criteria for distinguishing ‘pragmatic’ from ‘non-pragmatic’ implications and for separating the latter into ‘linguistic’ (‘semantic’ and ‘syntactical’) and ‘non-linguistic’ ones (2–3); consider (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations