Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Sex differences in mathematical reasoning ability among the intellectually talented: Further thoughts.Camilla Persson Benbow - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):196-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the testability of ECHO.D. C. Earle - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):474-474.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constraining tag-assignment from above and below.Michael R. W. Dawson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):400-402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Parallel processing: Giving up without a fight.John Duncan - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):402-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transcending “transcending…”.Stephen Jośe Hanson - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):656-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Physicians neglect base rates, and it matters.Robert M. Hamm - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):25-26.
    A recent study showed physicians' reasoning about a realistic case to be ignorant of base rate. It also showed physicians interpreting information pertinent to base rate differently, depending on whether it was presented early or late in the case. Although these adult reasoners might do better if given hints through talk of relative frequencies, this would not prove that they had no problem of base rate neglect.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Some remarks on the rationality of induction.Bipin Indurkhya - 1990 - Synthese 85 (1):95 - 114.
    This paper begins with a rigorous critique of David Stove''s recent bookThe Rationality of Induction. In it, Stove produced four different proofs to refute Hume''s sceptical thesis about induction. I show that Stove''s attempts to vindicate induction are unsuccessful. Three of his proofs refute theses that are not the sceptical thesis about induction at all. Stove''s fourth proof, which uses the sampling principle to justify one particular inductive inference, makes crucial use of an unstated assumption regarding randomness. Once this assumption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • SOAR as a world view, not a theory.Earl Hunt & R. Duncan Luce - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):447-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Exploring the evolution of complexity in signaling networks.John H. Holland - 2001 - Complexity 7 (2):34-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Analogical Mapping by Constraint Satisfaction.Keith J. Holyoak & Paul Thagard - 1989 - Cognitive Science 13 (3):295-355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   263 citations  
  • Are explanatory coherence and a connectionist model necessary?Jerry R. Hobbs - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):476-477.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Conceptual Integration Networks.Gilles Fauconnier & Mark Turner - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (2):133-187.
    Conceptual integration—“blending”—is a general cognitive operation on a par with analogy, recursion, mental modeling, conceptual categorization, and framing. It serves a variety of cognitive purposes. It is dynamic, supple, and active in the moment of thinking. It yields products that frequently become entrenched in conceptual structure and grammar, and it often performs new work on its previously entrenched products as inputs. Blending is easy to detect in spectacular cases but it is for the most part a routine, workaday process that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Modelling emergence.Francis Heylighen - 1991 - World Futures 32 (2):151-166.
    Emergence is defined as a process which cannot be described by a fixed model, consisting of invariant distinctions. Hence emergence must be described by a meta‐model, representing the transition of one model to another one by means of a distinction dynamics. The dynamics of distinctions is based on the processes of variation and selection, resulting in an invariant distinction, which constrains the variety and thus defines a new system. A classification of emergence processes is proposed, based on the following criteria: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Species intelligence: Hazards of structural parallels.Robert W. Hendersen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):78-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Ethics of Argumentation.Vasco Correia - 2012 - Informal Logic 32 (2):222-241.
    Normative theories of argumentation tend to assume that logical and dialectical rules suffice to ensure the rationality of argumentative discourse. Yet, in everyday debates people use arguments that seem valid in light of such rules but nonetheless biased and tendentious. This article seeks to show that the rationality of argumentation can only be fully promoted if we take into account its ethical dimension. To substantiate this claim, I review some of the empirical evidence indicating that people’s inferential reasoning is systematically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The bicameral retina at a glance.C. L. Hardin - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):405-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Preschoolers’ Induction of the Concept of Material Kind to Make Predictions: The Effects of Comparison and Linguistic Labels.Ilonca Hardy, Henrik Saalbach, Miriam Leuchter & Lennart Schalk - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:531503.
    Analogical reasoning by comparison is considered a special case of inductive reasoning, which is fundamental to the scientific method. By reasoning analogically, learners can abstract the underlying commonalities of several entities, thereby ignoring single objects’ superficial features. We tested whether different task environments designed to trigger analogical reasoning by comparison would support preschoolers’ induction of the concept of material kind to predict and explain objects’ floating or sinking as a central aspect of scientific reasoning. Specifically, in two experiments, we investigated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Connectionism in Pavlovian harness.George Graham - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy (Suppl.) 73 (S1):73-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Connectionism in Pavlovian harness.George Graham - 1991 - In Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 143--166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A cognitive theory without inductive learning.Lev Goldfarb - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):446-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Complementing explanation with induction.Clark Glymour - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):655-656.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Judgment under uncertainty: Evolution may not favor a probabilistic calculus.Lev R. Ginzburg, Charles Janson & Scott Ferson - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):24-25.
    The environment in which humans evolved is strongly and positively autocorrelated in space and time. Probabilistic judgments based on the assumption of independence may not yield evolutionarily adaptive behavior. A number of “faults” of human reasoning are not faulty under fuzzy arithmetic, a nonprobabilistic calculus of reasoning under uncertainty that may be closer to that underlying human decision making.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creativity theory: Detail and testability.K. J. Gilhooly - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):544-545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why do frequency formats improve Bayesian reasoning? Cognitive algorithms work on information, which needs representation.Gerd Gigerenzer - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):23-24.
    In contrast to traditional research on base-rate neglect, an ecologically-oriented research program would analyze the correspondence between cognitive algorithms and the nature of information in the environment. Bayesian computations turn out to be simpler when information is represented in frequency formats as opposed to the probability formats used in previous research. Frequency formats often enable even uninstructed subjects to perform Bayesian reasoning.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What does explanatory coherence explain?Ronald N. Giere - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):475-476.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Toward a cognitive psychology of science.Barry Gholson & Arthur Houts - 1989 - Social Epistemology 3 (2):107 – 127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are libraries intelligent?Michael T. Ghiselin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):78-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Searle’s Chinese room to the mathematics classroom: technical and cognitive mathematics.Dimitris Gavalas - 2006 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 26 (2):127-146.
    Employing Searle’s views, I begin by arguing that students of Mathematics behave similarly to machines that manage symbols using a set of rules. I then consider two types of Mathematics, which I call Cognitive Mathematics and Technical Mathematics respectively. The former type relates to concepts and meanings, logic and sense, whilst the latter relates to algorithms, heuristics, rules and application of various techniques. I claim that an upgrade in the school teaching of Cognitive Mathematics is necessary. The aim is to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • March of the models.Alan Garnham - 1994 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8 (1):37 – 39.
    This piece is a commentary on a target article by Phil Johnson-Laird, entitled: “A model theory of induction”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Coherence: Beyond constraint satisfaction.Gareth Gabrys & Alan Lesgold - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):475-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Base rates, stereotypes, and judgmental accuracy.David C. Funder - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):22-23.
    The base rate literature has an opposite twin in the social psychological literature on stereotypes, which concludes that people use their preexisting beliefs about probabilistic category attributes too much, rather than not enough. This ironic discrepancy arises because beliefs about category attributes enhance accuracy when the beliefs are accurate and diminish accuracy when they are not. To determine the accuracy of base rate/stereotype beliefs requires research that addresses specific content.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Creativity, madness, and extra strong Al.K. W. M. Fulford - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):542-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Unified theories of cognition good strategy?Nico H. Frijda & Jan Elshout - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):445-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • More packaging needed before tags are added.John Findlay & Robert Kentridge - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):404-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Affordance perception and the Y-magnocellular pathway.Chris Fields - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):403-404.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creative thinking presupposes the capacity for thought.James H. Fetzer - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):539-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What's in a link?Jerome A. Feldman - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):474-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tags is for kids.Jerome A. Feldman - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):403-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creative Argumentation: When and Why People Commit the Metaphoric Fallacy.Francesca Ervas, Antonio Ledda, Amitash Ojha, Giuseppe Antonio Pierro & Bipin Indurkhya - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Spatial ability: Not enough space to make a sex difference.John Eliot - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):196-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical praxis and logical theory part II: Selected roles for logicians.Edward A. Maziarz - 1988 - Philosophia Mathematica (2):21-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Societies Learn and yet the World is Hard to Change.Klaus Eder - 1999 - European Journal of Social Theory 2 (2):195-215.
    Evolution and learning are two analytically distinct concepts. People learn yet evolution (`change') does not necessarily take place. To clarify this problem the concept of learning is explicated. The first problem addressed is the question of who is learning. Here a shift from the single actor perspective to an interaction perspective is proposed (using Habermas and Luhmann as theoretical arguments for such a shift). Both, however, idealize the preconditions that interactants share while learning collectively. Against rationalist assumptions it is argued (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Concept Discovery in a Scientific Domain.Kevin Dunbar - 1993 - Cognitive Science 17 (3):397-434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • A Computational Account of the Development of the Generalization of Shape Information.Leonidas A. A. Doumas & John E. Hummel - 2010 - Cognitive Science 34 (4):698-712.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Unified cognitive theory is not comprehensive.P. C. Dodwell - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):443-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Thagard's theory of explanatory coherence the new logical positivism?Eric Dietrich - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):473-474.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Induction: Weak but essential.Thomas G. Dietterich - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):654-655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Robustness, optimality, and the handicap principle. [REVIEW]Jean-Louis Dessalles, Edouard Machery, Fiona Cowie & Jason Mckenzie Alexander - 2010 - Biology and Philosophy 25 (5):868-879.
    This symposium discusses J.-L. Dessalles's account of the evolution of language, which was presented in Why we Talk (OUP 2007).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unfortunately, scale and time matter.Kim C. Derrickson & Russell S. Greenberg - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teaching an old dog new tricks.Daniel C. Dennett - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):76-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation