Switch to: References

Citations of:

Semantic interpretation in generative grammar

Cambridge, Mass.,: MIT Press (1972)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Interpreting concatenation and concatenates.Paul M. Pietroski - 2006 - Philosophical Issues 16 (1):221–245.
    This paper presents a slightly modified version of the compositional semantics proposed in Events and Semantic Architecture (OUP 2005). Some readers may find this shorter version, which ignores issues about vagueness and causal constructions, easier to digest. The emphasis is on the treatments of plurality and quantification, and I assume at least some familiarity with more standard approaches.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Inference and information.Philip Pettit - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):727.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • ([How/why]) does linguistics matter to philosophy?Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 1977 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 15 (3):393-426.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemic modality and truth conditions.Anna Papafragou - unknown
    Within the linguistics literature it is often claimed that epistemic modality, unlike other kinds of modality, does not contribute to truth-conditional content. In this paper I challenge this view. I reanalyze a variety of arguments which have been used in support of the non-truth-conditional view and show that they can be handled on an alternative analysis of epistemic modality. # 2006 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • L'explication en grammaire transformationnelle.Claude Panaccio - 1979 - Dialogue 18 (3):307-341.
    Malgré les critiques de toutes sortes dont elle fut et dont elle est encore l'objet, la grammaire transformationnelle est devenue en vingt ans, sous l'impulsion de Noam Chomsky, le paradigme dominant de la linguistique contemporaine. Et, bien sûr, l'incroyable rapidité de cette ascension s'est accompagnée de nombreuses crises de croissance. Linguistes, philosophes et psychologues, ainsi amenés à s'interroger sur les fondements épistémologiques de cette étrange discipline, se sont heurtés à de redoutables énigmes métathéoriques: de quel domaine factuel la linguistique est-elle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inner and outer space: the neuroanatomical bases of spatially organized behaviors.David S. Olton - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):511-512.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The cognitive map as a hippocampus.John O'Keefe & Lynn Nadel - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):520-533.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Précis of O'Keefe & Nadel's The hippocampus as a cognitive map.John O'Keefe & Lynn Nadel - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):487-494.
    Theories of spatial cognition are derived from many sources. Psychologists are concerned with determining the features of the mind which, in combination with external inputs, produce our spatialized experience. A review of philosophical and other approaches has convinced us that the brain must come equipped to impose a three-dimensional Euclidean framework on experience – our analysis suggests that object re-identification may require such a framework. We identify this absolute, nonegocentric, spatial framework with a specific neural system centered in the hippocampus.A (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Time: a fourth dimension for the hippocampal cognitive map.Arthur J. Nonneman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):511-511.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceptual structure and syntax.Frederick J. Newmeyer - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):202-202.
    The syntactic structures of natural languages reflect conceptual categories more directly than they reflect communicative categories. This fact supports the main premise of the target article, namely, that the most important event in language evolution was the development of a hierarchical conceptual structure.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The scope of even and quantifier raising.Kimiko Nakanishi - 2012 - Natural Language Semantics 20 (2):115-136.
    This paper addresses the question of whether the preverbal even (VP-even) embedded in a nonfinite clause can take wide scope (e.g., Bill refused to even drink WATER). The paper presents novel evidence for wide scope VP-even that is independent of the presuppositions of even. The evidence is based on examples of antecedent-contained deletion (ACD), where embedded VP-even associates with a nominal constituent (or part of it) that raises out of the embedded clause via quantifier raising. Assuming that even must c-command (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intensionality and boundedness.Glyn Morrill - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (6):699 - 726.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The hippocampus and informational salience.John W. Moore - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):510-511.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Defense of Causal Invariantism.Martin Montminy & Andrew Russo - 2016 - Analytic Philosophy 57 (1):49-75.
    Causal contextualism holds that sentences of the form ‘c causes e’ have context-sensitive truth-conditions. We consider four arguments invoked by Jonathan Schaffer in favor of this view. First, he argues that his brand of contextualism helps solve puzzles about transitivity. Second, he contends that how one describes the relata of the causal relation sometimes affects the truth of one’s claim. Third, Schaffer invokes the phenomenon of contrastive focus to conclude that causal statements implicitly designate salient alternatives to the cause and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Apes and language: Human uniqueness again?Robert W. Mitchell & H. Lyn Miles - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):200-201.
    Wilkins & Wakefield's intriguing model of language evolution is deficient in evidence of human uniqueness in metaphorical matching, amodal representation, reference, conceptual structure, hierarchical organization, linguistic comprehension, sign use, laterality, and handedness. Primates show communicative reference, laterality, and handedness, and apes in particular show hierarchical organization, conceptual structure, cross-modal abilities, sign use, and displaced reference.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Race‐Based Parsing and Syntactic Disambiguation.Susan Weber McRoy & Graeme Hirst - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (3):313-353.
    We present a processing model that integrates same important psychological claims about the human sentence‐parsing mechanism: namely, that processing is influenced by limitations an working memory and by various syntactic preferences. The model uses time‐constraint information to resolve conflicting preferences in a psychologically plausible way. The starting paint far this proposal is the Sausage Machine model (Fodor & Frazier, 1980: Frazier & Fodor, 1978). From there, we attempt to overcome the original model's dependence an ad hoc aspects of its grammar, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A metalogical theory of natural language semantics.Michael Mccord & Arendse Bernth - 2004 - Linguistics and Philosophy 28 (1):73 - 116.
    We develop a framework for natural language semantics which handles intensionality via metalogical constructions and deals with degree truth values in an integrated way. We take an axiomatic set theory, ZF, as the foundation for semantic representations, but we make ZF a metalanguage for part of itself by embedding a language ℒ within ZF which is basically a copy of the part of ZF consisting of set expressions. This metalogical set-up is used for handling propositional attitude verbs (limited to believe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Focusing bound pronouns.Clemens Mayr - 2012 - Natural Language Semantics 20 (3):299-348.
    The presence of contrastive focus on pronouns interpreted as bound variables is puzzling. Bound variables do not refer, and it is therefore unclear how two of them can be made to contrast with each other. It is argued that this is a problem for both alternative-based accounts such as Rooth’s (Nat Lang Semantics 1:75–116, 1992) and givenness-based ones such as Schwarzschild’s (Nat Lang Semantics 7:141–177, 1999). The present paper shows that previous approaches to this puzzle face an empirical problem, namely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The hominid tool-language connection: Some missing evolutionary links?A. Maryanski - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):199-200.
    This commentary criticizes Wilkins & Wakefield's thesis that the neurological precursors of language provide a cognitive Rubicon to linguistically divide human from nonhuman primates. A causal model of their theory is presented, followed by a discussion of the relationship between brain expansion and tool use, Broca's area and the parietaloccipital-temporal junction (POT).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to have a metalinguistic dispute.Poppy Mankowitz - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):5603-5622.
    There has been recent interest in the idea that speakers who appear to be having a verbal dispute may in fact be engaged in a metalinguistic negotiation: they are communicating information about how they believe an expression should be used. For example, individuals involved in a dispute about whether a racehorse is an athlete might be communicating their diverging views about how ‘athlete’ should be used. While many have argued that metalinguistic negotiation is a pervasive feature of philosophical and everyday (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Explaining the Actuality Operator Away.John Mackay - 2017 - Philosophical Quarterly 67 (269):709-21.
    I argue that ‘actually’ does not have a reading according to which it is synonymous with the actuality operator of modal logic, and propose an alternative account of ‘actually’. The cases that have been thought to show that ‘actually’ is synonymous with the actuality operator are modal and counterfactual sentences in which an embedded clause's evaluation is held fixed at the world of the context. In these cases, though, this embedded clause's evaluation is not due to the presence of ‘actually’. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Semiogenesis as a continuous, not a discrete, phenomenon.Jo Liska - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):198-199.
    This commentary confronts one of the central tenets advanced in Wilkins & Wakefield's target article: By adopting a very narrow perspective on language, the authors have effectively limited discussion of earlier linguistic capabilities thought to be at least facilitative of, if not prerequisite to language defined as a An alternative conceptualization for describing semiogenesis is offered.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Negative polarity and grammatical representation.Marcia C. Linebarger - 1987 - Linguistics and Philosophy 10 (3):325 - 387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Manual versus speech motor control and the evolution of language.Philip Lieberman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):197-198.
    Inferences made from endocasts of fossil skulls cannot provide information on the function of particular neocortical areas or the subcortical pathways to prefrontal cortex that form part of the neural substrate for speech, syntax, and certain aspects of cognition. The neural bases of syntax cannot be disassociated from “communication.” Manual motor control was probably a preadaptive factor in the evolution of humansyntactic ability, but neurophysiological data on living humans show that speech motor control and syntax are more closely linked. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Children's command of quantification.Jeffrey Lidz & Julien Musolino - 2002 - Cognition 84 (2):113-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • What model theoretic semantics cannot do?Ernest Lepore - 1983 - Synthese 54 (2):167 - 187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Coming of age in Olduvai and the Zaire rain forest.Justin Leiber - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):196-197.
    ProbablyHomo habilisis two species not one; similarly for Pan troglodytes. Although amenable to training, in naturePan paniscusmay be a “specialized insular dwarf.” Language is uniquely human, but symbolic behavior and intelligence are widespread among animals with little respect for phylogenetic closeness toHomo sapiens.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Ought” and Intensionality.Junhyo Lee - 2021 - Synthese 199:4621-4643.
    The syntactic structure of the deontic “ought” has been much debated in philosophy and linguistics. Schroeder argues that the deontic “ought” is syntactically ambiguous in the sense that it can be associated with either a control or raising construction. He distinguishes between deliberative and evaluative “ought”s and argues that the deliberative “ought” is control while the evaluative “ought” is raising. However, if there is a control sense of “ought,” it implies that there is a sense of “ought” in which the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Implicit arguments in situation semantics.Richard K. Larson - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (2):169 - 201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Imperatives and Modals.Paul Portner - 2007 - Natural Language Semantics 15 (4):351-383.
    Imperatives may be interpreted with many subvarieties of directive force, for example as orders, invitations, or pieces of advice. I argue that the range of meanings that imperatives can convey should be identified with the variety of interpretations that are possible for non-dynamic root modals (what I call ‘priority modals’), including deontic, bouletic, and teleological readings. This paper presents an analysis of the relationship between imperatives and priority modals in discourse which asserts that, just as declaratives contribute to the Common (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Resolution of quantifier scope ambiguities.Howard S. Kurtzman & Maryellen C. MacDonald - 1993 - Cognition 48 (3):243-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Discourse and information structure.Ivana Kruijff-korbayová & Mark Steedman - 2003 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 12 (3):249-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An investigation of the lumps of thought.Angelika Kratzer - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (5):607 - 653.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • Sublexical modality and the structure of lexical semantic representations.Jean-Pierre Koenig & Anthony R. Davis - 2001 - Linguistics and Philosophy 24 (1):71-124.
    This paper argues for a largely unnoted distinction between relational and modal components in the lexical semantics of verbs. Wehypothesize that many verbs encode two kinds of semantic information:a relationship among participants in a situation and a subset ofcircumstances or time indices at which this relationship isevaluated. The latter we term sublexical modality.We show that linking regularities between semantic arguments andsyntactic functions provide corroborating evidence in favor of thissemantic distinction, noting cases in which the semantic groundingof linking through participant-role properties (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hungarian Structural Focus: Accessibility to Focused Elements and Their Alternatives in Working Memory and Delayed Recognition Memory.Tamás Káldi, Ágnes Szöllösi & Anna Babarczy - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    The present work investigates the memory accessibility of linguistically focused elements and the representation of the alternatives for these elements in Working Memory and in delayed recognition memory in the case of the Hungarian pre-verbal focus construction. In two probe recognition experiments we presented preVf and corresponding focusless neutral sentences embedded in five-sentence stories. Stories were followed by the presentation of sentence probes in one of three conditions: the probe was identical to the original sentence in the story, the focused (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deriving the contrastiveness of contrastive -nun in Korean.Jieun Kim - 2018 - Linguistics and Philosophy 41 (4):457-482.
    The Korean particle -nun combined with an accent indicates contrast :269–320, 1972; Heycock, in: Merce Proceedings of NELS, vol 24, pp 159–187, 1993; in: Miyagawa, Saito Handbook of Japanese linguistics, Oxford University Press, Cambridge, 2007; Hara, in: Dekker, Franke Fifteenth Amsterdam colloquium, Universiteit van Amsterdam, pp 101–106, 2006; Lee, in: Lee, Gordon, Büring Topic and focus: meaning and intonation from a crosslinguistic perspective. Springer, Berlin, 2003; Tomioka, in: Zimmermann, Fery Information structure, Oxford University Press, Cambridge, pp 115–138, 2009, among many (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Production and perception of contrast: The case of the rise-fall contour in German.Frank Kügler & Anja Gollrad - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:81380.
    This study investigates the phonetics of German nuclear rise-fall contours in relation to contexts that trigger either a contrastive or a non-contrastive interpretation in the answer. A rise-fall contour can be conceived of a tonal sequence of L-H-L. A production study elicited target sentences in contrastive and non-contrastive contexts. The majority of cases realized showed a nuclear rise-fall contour. The acoustic analysis of these contours revealed a significant effect of contrastiveness on the height / alignment of the accent peak as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hippocampus and memory.Raymond P. Kesner - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):509-510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Coherence and the resolution of ellipsis.Andrew Kehler - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (6):533-575.
    Despite the attention that various forms of ellipsis have received inthe literature, the conditions under which a representation of anutterance may serve as a suitable referent for interpreting subsequentelliptical forms remain poorly understood. This fundamental questionremains as a point of contention, particularly because there are datato support various conflicting approaches that attempt to characterizethese conditions within a single module of language processing. Weshow a previously unnoticed pattern in VP-ellipsis data with respectto the type of coherence relation extant between the antecedentand (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Beyond the Frege boundary.Edward L. Keenan - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (2):199-221.
    In sentences like Every teacher laughed we think of every teacher as a unary (=type (1)) quantifier - it expresses a property of one place predicate denotations. In variable binding terms, unary quantifiers bind one variable. Two applications of unary quantifiers, as in the interpretation of No student likes every teacher, determine a binary (= type (2)) quantifier; they express properties of two place predicate denotations. In variable binding terms they bind two variables. We call a binary quantifier Fregean (or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A note on contrast.Roni Katzir - 2013 - Natural Language Semantics 21 (4):333-343.
    The semantics of association with focus and the pragmatic conditions governing the appropriateness of focus in discourse are usually taken to depend on focus alternatives. According to a common view, these alternatives are generated by a permissive process. This permissive view has been challenged by Michael Wagner, who has noted that certain alternatives are systematically excluded from consideration. Wagner describes a more restrictive view, on which only contrastive alternatives are relevant for association with focus and for the appropriateness of focus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Structural and semantic constraints on the resolution of pronouns and reflexives.Elsi Kaiser, Jeffrey T. Runner, Rachel S. Sussman & Michael K. Tanenhaus - 2009 - Cognition 112 (1):55-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Without 'Focus'.Nirit Kadmon & Aldo Sevi - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:18.
    It is widely accepted that a notion of 'focus', more or less as conceived of in Jackendoff , must be incorporated into our theory of grammar, as a means of accounting for certain observed correlations between prosodic facts and semantic/pragmatic facts. In this paper, we put forth the somewhat radical idea that the time has come to give up this customary view, and eliminate 'focus' from our theory of grammar. We argue that such a move is both economical and fruitful.Research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Meaning of Modality.P. N. Johnson-Laird - 1978 - Cognitive Science 2 (1):17-26.
    This paper describes a semantics for modal terms such as can and may that is intended to model the mental representation of their meaning. The basic assumption of the theory is that the evaluation of a modal assertion involves an attempted mental construction of a specified alternative to a given situation rather than the separate evaluation of each member of a set of possible alternatives as would be required by a “possible worlds” semantics. The theory leads to the conclusion that, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A semantic account of quantifier-induced intervention effects in Chinese why-questions.Dawei Jin - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (4):345-387.
    This paper revisits intervention effects in Mandarin Chinese why-questions. I present a novel empirical generalization, in which it is shown that the ability for quantifiers to induce intervention hinges upon their monotonicity and their ability to be interpreted as topics. I then propose a semantic account of intervention that correlates topicality with the monotone properties of intervening operators. A crucial assumption in this account is that why-questions in Chinese are idiosyncratic, in that the Chinese equivalent of why directly merges at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Issues in neo- and paleoneurology of language.Harry J. Jerison - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):195-196.
    Wilkins and Wakefield's hypothesis that language is fundamentally a cognitive rather than cominunicational adaptation is reasonable, but there are flaws in their anatomical and fossil evidence. Their analysis of reorganization also needs clarification. Finally, the origin of language ability must have occurred with australopithecine rather than habiline adaptations on entry into the novel hominid adaptive zone.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Considerations in evaluating the cognitive mapping theory of hippocampal function.Leonard E. Jarrard - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):509-509.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • II. An unfavorable review oflanguage, sense and nonsense∗.James Bogen - 1985 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 28 (1-4):467-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is a concept, that a person may grasp it?Ray Jackendoff - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (1-2):68-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • What is a cognitive map?Ray Jackendoff - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):507-509.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark