Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Liberal Paradox: Some Interpretations When Rights Are Represented As Game Forms.Prasanta K. Pattanaik - 1996 - Analyse & Kritik 18 (1):38-53.
    The paper seeks to interpret the liberal paradox in a framework where individual rights are represented as game forms. Several close counterparts, in this framework, of Sen’s theorem are considered, and their intuitive significance is discussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ocho desiderata metodológicos de las teorías sociales normativas.Antoni Dümenech - 1998 - Isegoría 18:115-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Equal Opportunity or Equal Social Outcome?Marc Fleurbaey - 1995 - Economics and Philosophy 11 (1):25.
    John Rawls's work has greatly contributed to rehabilitating equality as a basic social value, after decades of utilitarian hegemony,particularly in normative economics, but Rawls also emphasized that full equality of welfare is not an adequate goal either. This thesis was echoed in Dworkin's famous twin papers on equality, and it is now widely accepted that egalitarianism must be selective. The bulk of the debate on ‘Equality of What?’ thus deals with what variables ought to be submitted for selection and how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • J.S. Mill and market harms: a response to Endörfer.Ben Saunders - forthcoming - Economics and Philosophy:1-6.
    Endörfer has recently argued that proponents of the harm principle are wrong to exempt market harms as potential justifications for state interference. I argue that – contrary to suggestions in Endörfer’s article – John Stuart Mill did not exempt market harms from his harm principle. On Mill’s view, the state can (as a matter of principle) legitimately interfere with free markets to prevent market harms where they occur but, on the whole, it is better policy not to interfere. Mill’s general (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rights to Liberty in Purely Private Matters: Part II.Jonathan Riley - 1990 - Economics and Philosophy 6 (1):27-64.
    A claim that certain purely private matters should be beyond the reach of society's laws, moral rules, and other customs is central to the distinctive liberalism of John Stuart Mill. On Liberty, perhaps the most eloquent defense of individual liberty ever written, laments the hostility allegedly displayed in modern mass societies toward “the right of each individual to act [in private matters] as seems good to his judgement and inclinations”. In Mill's view, a free society must design its institutions with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Diversity and rights: a social choice-theoretic analysis of the possibility of public reason.Hun Chung & Brian Kogelmann - 2020 - Synthese 197 (2):839-865.
    Public reason liberalism takes as its starting point the deep and irreconcilable diversity we find characterizing liberal societies. This deep and irreconcilable diversity creates problems for social order. One method for adjudicating these conflicts is through the use of rights. This paper is about the ability of such rights to adjudicate disputes when perspectival disagreements—or disagreements over how to categorize objects in the world—obtain. We present both formal possibility and impossibility results for rights structures under varying degrees of perspectival diversity. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations