Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Mathematical arguments in context.Jean Paul Van Bendegem & Bart Van Kerkhove - 2009 - Foundations of Science 14 (1-2):45-57.
    Except in very poor mathematical contexts, mathematical arguments do not stand in isolation of other mathematical arguments. Rather, they form trains of formal and informal arguments, adding up to interconnected theorems, theories and eventually entire fields. This paper critically comments on some common views on the relation between formal and informal mathematical arguments, most particularly applications of Toulmin’s argumentation model, and launches a number of alternative ideas of presentation inviting the contextualization of pieces of mathematical reasoning within encompassing bodies of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ether and theory of elasticity in Beltrami's work.Rossana Tazzioli - 1993 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 46 (1):1-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Energy: Learning from the Past.Fabio Bevilacqua - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (6):1231-1243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wigner’s Puzzle for Mathematical Naturalism.Sorin Bangu - 2009 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 23 (3):245-263.
    I argue that a recent version of the doctrine of mathematical naturalism faces difficulties arising in connection with Wigner's old puzzle about the applicability of mathematics to natural science. I discuss the strategies to solve the puzzle and I show that they may not be available to the naturalist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Taking mathematical fictions seriously.Michael Liston - 1993 - Synthese 95 (3):433 - 458.
    I argue on the basis of an example, Fourier theory applied to the problem of vibration, that Field's program for nominalizing science is unlikely to succeed generally, since no nominalistic variant will provide us with the kind of physical insight into the phenomena that the standard theory supplies. Consideration of the same example also shows, I argue, that some of the motivation for mathematical fictionalism, particularly the alleged problem of cognitive access, is more apparent than real.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • In defence of indispensability.Mark Colyvan - 1998 - Philosophia Mathematica 6 (1):39-62.
    Indispensability arguments for realism about mathematical entities have come under serious attack in recent years. To my mind the most profound attack has come from Penelope Maddy, who argues that scientific/mathematical practice doesn't support the key premise of the indispensability argument, that is, that we ought to have ontological commitment to those entities that are indispensable to our best scientific theories. In this paper I defend the Quine/Putnam indispensability argument against Maddy's objections.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Historical evolution of the concept of homotopic paths.Ria Vanden Eynde - 1992 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 45 (2):127-188.
    The historical evolution of the homotopy concept for paths illustrates how the introduction of a concept (be it implicit or explicit) depends upon the interests of the mathematicians concerned and how it gradually acquires a more satisfactory definition. In our case the equivalence of paths first meant for certain mathematicians that they led to the same value of the integral of a given function or that they led to the same value of a multiple-valued function. (See for instance [Cau], [Pui], (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Representing the World with Inconsistent Mathematics.Colin McCullough-Benner - 2019 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (4):1331-1358.
    According to standard accounts of mathematical representations of physical phenomena, positing structure-preserving mappings between a physical target system and the structure picked out by a mathematical theory is essential to such representations. In this paper, I argue that these accounts fail to give a satisfactory explanation of scientific representations that make use of inconsistent mathematical theories and present an alternative, robustly inferential account of mathematical representation that provides not just a better explanation of applications of inconsistent mathematics, but also a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Beauty in science: a new model of the role of aesthetic evaluations in science. [REVIEW]Ulianov Montano - 2013 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3 (2):133-156.
    In Beauty and Revolution in Science, James McAllister advances a rationalistic picture of science in which scientific progress is explained in terms of aesthetic evaluations of scientific theories. Here I present a new model of aesthetic evaluations by revising McAllister’s core idea of the aesthetic induction. I point out that the aesthetic induction suffers from anomalies and theoretical inconsistencies and propose a model free from such problems. The new model is based, on the one hand, on McAllister’s original model and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Nested realities and human consciousness: The paradoxical expression of evolutionary process.Paul C. Wohlmuth - 1988 - World Futures 25 (3):199-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Karl Menger as a philosopher. [REVIEW]Donald Gillies - 1981 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (2):183-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The calculus as algebraic analysis: Some observations on mathematical analysis in the 18th century.Craig G. Fraser - 1989 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 39 (4):317-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The development of asymptotic solutions of linear ordinary differential equations, 1817–1920.Arthur Schlissel - 1977 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 16 (4):307-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pasch's empiricism as methodological structuralism.Dirk Schlimm - 2020 - In Erich H. Reck & Georg Schiemer (eds.), The Pre-History of Mathematical Structuralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 80-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Joseph H. M. Wedderburn and the structure theory of algebras.Karen Hunger Parshall - 1985 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 32 (3):223-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Poncelet’s porism: a long story of renewed discoveries, I.Andrea Del Centina - 2016 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 70 (1):1-122.
    In 1813, J.-V. Poncelet discovered that if there exists a polygon of n-sides, which is inscribed in a given conic and circumscribed about another conic, then infinitely many such polygons exist. This theorem became known as Poncelet’s porism, and the related polygons were called Poncelet’s polygons. In this article, we trace the history of the research about the existence of such polygons, from the “prehistorical” work of W. Chapple, of the middle of the eighteenth century, to the modern approach of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Using History to Teach Mathematics: The Case of Logarithms.Evangelos N. Panagiotou - 2011 - Science & Education 20 (1):1-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Assaying lakatos's philosophy of mathematics.David Corfield - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (1):99-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Minimal Axioms for Peirce's Triadic Logic.Atwell R. Turquette - 1976 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 22 (1):169-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Historians and Philosophers of Logic: Are They Compatible? The Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem as a Case Study.Gregory H. Moore - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):169-180.
    This paper combines personal reminiscences of the philosopher John Corcoran with a discussion of certain conflicts between historians of logic and philosophers of logic. Some mistaken claims about the history of the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem are analyzed in detail and corrected.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Lebesgue’s criticism of Carl Neumann’s method in potential theory.Ivan Netuka - 2020 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 74 (1):77-108.
    In the 1870s, Carl Neumann proposed the so-called method of the arithmetic mean for solving the Dirichlet problem on convex domains. Neumann’s approach was considered at the time to be a reliable existence proof, following Weierstrass’s criticism of the Dirichlet principle. However, in 1937 H. Lebesgue pointed out a serious gap in Neumann’s proof. Curiously, the erroneous argument once again involved confusion between the notions of infimum and minimum. The objective of this paper is to show that Lebesgue’s sharp criticism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thales's sure path.David Sherry - 1999 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 30 (4):621-650.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Continuity in nature and in mathematics: Boltzmann and Poincaré.Marij van Strien - 2015 - Synthese 192 (10):3275-3295.
    The development of rigorous foundations of differential calculus in the course of the nineteenth century led to concerns among physicists about its applicability in physics. Through this development, differential calculus was made independent of empirical and intuitive notions of continuity, and based instead on strictly mathematical conditions of continuity. However, for Boltzmann and Poincaré, the applicability of mathematics in physics depended on whether there is a basis in physics, intuition or experience for the fundamental axioms of mathematics—and this meant that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The reformulation of the concept of predicativity according to Poincaré.Vecchio Junior & Jacintho Del - 2013 - Scientiae Studia 11 (2):391-416.
    Este texto introduz a tradução do discurso de intitulado "Sobre os números transfinitos" ("Über transfinite Zahlen"), proferido por Henri Poincaré em 27 de abril de 1909, na Universidade de Göttingen. Após uma breve apresentação do pensamento do autor acerca dos fundamentos da aritmética, procura-se citar os aspectos mais relevantes da chamada crise dos fundamentos da matemática, para então introduzir a reformulação do conceito de predicatividade aventada no referido discurso sobre números transfinitos, contribuição compreendida como um recurso teórico necessário para a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ambiguities of Fundamental Concepts in Mathematical Analysis During the Mid-nineteenth Century.Kajsa Bråting - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (4):301-320.
    In this paper we consider the major development of mathematical analysis during the mid-nineteenth century. On the basis of Jahnke’s (Hist Math 20(3):265–284, 1993 ) distinction between considering mathematics as an empirical science based on time and space and considering mathematics as a purely conceptual science we discuss the Swedish nineteenth century mathematician E.G. Björling’s general view of real- and complexvalued functions. We argue that Björling had a tendency to sometimes consider mathematical objects in a naturalistic way. One example is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The emergence of the Weierstrassian approach to complex analysis.Kenneth R. Manning - 1975 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 14 (4):297-383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reflexiones sobre el lenguaje matemático y su incidencia en el aprendizaje significativo / Reflections on the mathematical language and its incidence in the significant learning.Luis Alberto Puga Peña, Jhony Mauro Rodriguez Orozco & Alba Marlene Toledo Delgado - 2016 - Sophia. Colección de Filosofía de la Educación 20:197-220.
    El análisis de la relación entre lenguaje, conocimiento y aprendizaje se presenta como una oportunidad para contribuir en la mejora de los procesos educativos, es así, que éste artículo presenta importantes reflexiones sobre la incidencia del lenguaje matemático y el aprendizaje significativo de esta ciencia. Existen muchos trabajos que han dado directrices para mejorar la labor de los actores del proceso educativo, se han propuesto la aplicación de metodologías activas para construir el conocimiento, la utilización de las TIC como recursos (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Concept Formation and Concept Grounding.Jörgen Sjögren & Christian Bennet - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (3):827-839.
    Recently Carrie S. Jenkins formulated an epistemology of mathematics, or rather arithmetic, respecting apriorism, empiricism, and realism. Central is an idea of concept grounding. The adequacy of this idea has been questioned e.g. concerning the grounding of the mathematically central concept of set (or class), and of composite concepts. In this paper we present a view of concept formation in mathematics, based on ideas from Carnap, leading to modifications of Jenkins’s epistemology that may solve some problematic issues with her ideas. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Book Reviews: George Lakoff and Rafael E. Núñez, Where Mathematics Comes From, New York: Basic Books, 2000, xvii+493 pp., $30.00, ISBN 0-46503-770-4. [REVIEW]Gary M. Shute - 2004 - Minds and Machines 15 (1):118-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La teoría de los invariantes y el espacio intuitivo en Der Raum de Rudolf Carnap.Álvaro J. Peláez Cedrés - 2008 - Análisis Filosófico 28 (2):175-203.
    La consecuencia más difundida de la revolución en la geometría del siglo XIX es aquella que afirma que después de dichos cambios ya nada quedaría de la vieja noción de espacio como "forma de la intuición sensible", ni de la geometría como "condición trascendental" de la posibilidad de la experiencia. Este artículo se ocupa del intento de Rudolf Carnap por articular una concepción del espacio intuitivo que, al tiempo que se mantiene dentro del paradigma kantiano se hace eco de algunos (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beltrami's model and the independence of the parallel postulate.J. Scanlan Michael - 1988 - History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (1):13-34.
    E. Beltrami in 1868 did not intend to prove the consistency of non-euclidean plane geometry nor the independence of the euclidean parallel postulate. His approach would have been unsuccessful if so intended. J. Hoüel in 1870 described the relevance of Beltrami's work to the issue of the independence of the euclidean parallel postulate. Hoüel's method is different from the independence proofs using reinterpretation of terms deployed by Peano about 1890, chiefly in using a fixed interpretation for non-logical terms. Comparing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Practical reasoning and the witnessably rigorous proof.Eric Livingston - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1-2):2277-2291.
    This paper introduces an anthropological approach to the foundations of mathematics. Traditionally, the philosophy of mathematics has focused on the nature and origins of mathematical truth. Mathematicians, however, treat mathematical arguments as determining mathematical truth: if an argument is found to describe a witnessably rigorous proof of a theorem, that theorem is considered—until the need for further examination arises—to be true. The anthropological question is how mathematicians, as a practical matter and as a matter of mathematical practice, make such determinations. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Piola’s contribution to continuum mechanics.Giuseppe C. Ruta & Danilo Capecchi - 2007 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 61 (4):303-342.
    This paper examines the contribution of Gabrio Piola to continuum mechanics.Though he was undoubtably a skilled mathematician and a good mechanician, little is commonly known about his papers within the international scientific community, principally because a large part of the Italian school of mechanics was isolated in the first half of the XIXth century.We examine and comment on Piola’s most important papers, and compare them with those of his contemporaries Cauchy, Poisson and Kirchhoff.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Frege and his groups.Tuomo Aho - 1998 - History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (3):137-151.
    Frege's docent's dissertation Rechnungsmethoden, die sich auf eine Erweiterung des Grössenbegriffes gründen(1874) contains indications of a bold attempt to extend arithmetic. According to it, arithmetic means the science of magnitude, and magnitude must be understood structurally without intuitive support. The main thing is insight into the formal structure of the operation of ?addition?. It turns out that a general ?magnitude domain? coincides with a (commutative) group. This is an interesting connection with simultaneous developments in abstract algebra. As his main application, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Riemann and the theory of electrical phenomena: Nobili’s rings.Thomas Archibald - 1991 - Centaurus 34 (3):247--271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Historical development of the foundations of mathematics: Course description.Robert L. Brabenec - 1994 - Science & Education 3 (3):295-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scientific realism and perception. [REVIEW]Raimo Tuomela - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1):87-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book reviews: David Papineau,thinking about consciousness, clarendon press (oxford university press), 2002, XIV + 266 pp., $35.00 (hardcover), ISBN 0-19924-382-. [REVIEW]Richard Wyatt - 2005 - Minds and Machines 15 (1):113-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analyse et géométrie, histoire des courbes gauches De Clairaut à Darboux.Jean Delcourt - 2011 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 65 (3):229-293.
    RésuméCet article est consacré à l’histoire de la théorie locale des courbes “à double courbure”. Initiée par Clairaut en 1731, cette théorie se développe en parallèle à la théorie des surfaces et trouve son achèvement avec les formules de Serret et Frenet et leur interprétation par Darboux, en 1887. Au delà de l’analyse des contributions de nombreux mathématiciens, parmi lesquels Monge bien sûr mais aussi Fourier, Lagrange et Cauchy, notre étude donne un regard particulier sur l’évolution conjointe de l’Analyse et (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Zur Differenzierbarkeit stetiger Funktionen — Ampère's Beweis und seine Folgen.Klaus Volkert - 1989 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 40 (1):37-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Applied versus situated mathematics in ancient Egypt: bridging the gap between theory and practice.Sandra Visokolskis & Héctor Horacio Gerván - 2022 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 (1):1-30.
    This historiographical study aims at introducing the category of “situated mathematics” to the case of Ancient Egypt. However, unlike Situated Learning Theory, which is based on ethnographic relativity, in this paper, the goal is to analyze a mathematical craft knowledge based on concrete particulars and case studies, which is ubiquitous in all human activity, and which even covers, as a specific case, the Hellenistic style, where theoretical constructs do not stand apart from practice, but instead remain grounded in it.The historiographic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Die mathematischen und philosophischen Grundlagen des Weierstraßschen Zahlbegriffs zwischen Bolzano und Cantor.Detlef D. Spalt - 1991 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 41 (4):311-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • German Philosophy of Mathematics from Gauss to Hilbert.Donald Gillies - 1999 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 44:167-192.
    Suppose we were to ask some students of philosophy to imagine a typical book of classical German philosophy and describe its general style and character, how might they reply? I suspect that they would answer somewhat as follows. The book would be long and heavy, it would be written in a complicated style which employed only very abstract terms, and it would be extremely difficult to understand. At all events a description of this kind does indeed fit many famous works (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pasch’s philosophy of mathematics.Dirk Schlimm - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):93-118.
    Moritz Pasch (1843ber neuere Geometrie (1882), in which he also clearly formulated the view that deductions must be independent from the meanings of the nonlogical terms involved. Pasch also presented in these lectures the main tenets of his philosophy of mathematics, which he continued to elaborate on throughout the rest of his life. This philosophy is quite unique in combining a deductivist methodology with a radically empiricist epistemology for mathematics. By taking into consideration publications from the entire span of Paschs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Egg-Forms and Measure-Bodies: Different Mathematical Practices in the Early History of the Modern Theory of Convexity.Tinne Hoff Kjeldsen - 2009 - Science in Context 22 (1):85-113.
    ArgumentTwo simultaneous episodes in late nineteenth-century mathematical research, one by Karl Hermann Brunn and another by Hermann Minkowski, have been described as the origin of the theory of convex bodies. This article aims to understand and explain how and why the concept of such bodies emerged in these two trajectories of mathematical research; and why Minkowski's – and not Brunn's – strand of thought led to the development of a theory of convexity. Concrete pieces of Brunn's and Minkowski's mathematical work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Logic Semantics with the Potential Infinite.Theodore Hailperin - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (2):145-159.
    A form of quantification logic referred to by the author in earlier papers as being 'ontologically neutral' still made use of the actual infinite in its semantics. Here it is shown that one can have, if one desires, a formal logic that refers in its semantics only to the potential infinite. Included are two new quantifiers generalizing the sentential connectives, equivalence and non-equivalence. There are thus new avenues opening up for exploration in both quantification logic and semantics of the infinite.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against the Topologists: Essay Review of New Foundations for Physical Gemoetry. [REVIEW]Samuel C. Fletcher - 2017 - Philosophy of Science 84 (3):595-603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Logic of Mathematical Discovery Vs. the Logical Structure of Mathematics.Solomon Feferman - 1978 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978 (2):309-327.
    Mathematics offers us a puzzling contrast. On the one hand it is supposed to be the paradigm of certain and final knowledge: not fixed to be sure, but a steadily accumulating coherent body of truths obtained by successive deduction from the most evident truths. By the intricate combination and recombination of elementary steps one is led incontrovertibly from what is trivial and unremarkable to what can be non-trivial and surprising.On the other hand, the actual development of mathematics reveals a history (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Whittaker’s analytical dynamics: a biography.S. C. Coutinho - 2014 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 68 (3):355-407.
    Originally published in 1904, Whittaker’s A Treatise on the Analytical Dynamics of Particles and Rigid Bodies soon became a classic of the subject and has remained in print for most of these 108 years. In this paper, we follow the book as it develops from a report that Whittaker wrote for the British Society for the Advancement of Science to its influence on Dirac’s version of quantum mechanics in the 1920s and beyond.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation