Switch to: References

Citations of:

A notion of mechanistic theory

Synthese 29 (1-4):11 - 26 (1974)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Computability and physical theories.Robert Geroch & James B. Hartle - 1986 - Foundations of Physics 16 (6):533-550.
    The familiar theories of physics have the feature that the application of the theory to make predictions in specific circumstances can be done by means of an algorithm. We propose a more precise formulation of this feature—one based on the issue of whether or not the physically measurable numbers predicted by the theory are computable in the mathematical sense. Applying this formulation to one approach to a quantum theory of gravity, there are found indications that there may exist no such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • The wave equation with computable initial data whose unique solution is nowhere computable.Marian B. Pour-El & Ning Zhong - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (4):499-509.
    We give a rough statement of the main result. Let D be a compact subset of ℝ3× ℝ. The propagation u of a wave can be noncomputable in any neighborhood of any point of D even though the initial conditions which determine the wave propagation uniquely are computable. A precise statement of the result appears below.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Beyond the universal Turing machine.Jack Copeland - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (1):46-67.
    We describe an emerging field, that of nonclassical computability and nonclassical computing machinery. According to the nonclassicist, the set of well-defined computations is not exhausted by the computations that can be carried out by a Turing machine. We provide an overview of the field and a philosophical defence of its foundations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Physical Computation: How General are Gandy’s Principles for Mechanisms?B. Jack Copeland & Oron Shagrir - 2007 - Minds and Machines 17 (2):217-231.
    What are the limits of physical computation? In his ‘Church’s Thesis and Principles for Mechanisms’, Turing’s student Robin Gandy proved that any machine satisfying four idealised physical ‘principles’ is equivalent to some Turing machine. Gandy’s four principles in effect define a class of computing machines (‘Gandy machines’). Our question is: What is the relationship of this class to the class of all (ideal) physical computing machines? Gandy himself suggests that the relationship is identity. We do not share this view. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Turing's o-machines, Searle, Penrose, and the brain.Jack Copeland - 1998 - Analysis 58 (2):128-138.
    In his PhD thesis (1938) Turing introduced what he described as 'a new kind of machine'. He called these 'O-machines'. The present paper employs Turing's concept against a number of currently fashionable positions in the philosophy of mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Qualifying Qualia Through the Skyhook Test.Tere Vadén - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (2):149-169.
    If we are to preserve qualia, one possibility is to take the current academic, philosophical, and theoretical notion less seriously and current natural science and some pre-theoretical intuitions about qualia more seriously. Dennett (1997) is instrumental in showing how ideas of the intrinsicalness and privacy of qualia are misguided and those of ineffability and immediacy misinterpreted. However, by combining ideas of non-mechanicalness used in contemporary natural science with the pre-theoretical idea that qualia are special because they are unique, we get (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is the human mind a Turing machine?D. King - 1996 - Synthese 108 (3):379-89.
    In this paper I discuss the topics of mechanism and algorithmicity. I emphasise that a characterisation of algorithmicity such as the Turing machine is iterative; and I argue that if the human mind can solve problems that no Turing machine can, the mind must depend on some non-iterative principle — in fact, Cantor's second principle of generation, a principle of the actual infinite rather than the potential infinite of Turing machines. But as there has been theorisation that all physical systems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Is “Physical Randomness” Just Indeterminism in Disguise?Paul W. Humphreys - 1978 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978 (2):98-113.
    The topic of this session is “physical randomness”. It might be doubted whether such a subject exists, for definitions of randomness have hitherto almost all been mathematical in nature. The only exceptions of which I am aware are the preceding paper by Benioff and a paper by Wesley Salmon. These attempts to inject some empirical content into randomness are highly desirable. But anyone attempting to formulate a physically based definition of randomness should at some point make clear what the connection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Undecidability of the Spectral Gap: An Epistemological Look.Emiliano Ippoliti & Sergio Caprara - 2021 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 52 (1):157-170.
    The results of Cubitt et al. on the spectral gap problem add a new chapter to the issue of undecidability in physics, as they show that it is impossible to decide whether the Hamiltonian of a quantum many-body system is gapped or gapless. This implies, amongst other things, that a reductionist viewpoint would be untenable. In this paper, we examine their proof and a few philosophical implications, in particular ones regarding models and limitative results. In more detail, we examine the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Technology and Mathematics.Sven Ove Hansson - 2020 - Philosophy and Technology 33 (1):117-139.
    In spite of their practical importance, the connections between technology and mathematics have not received much scholarly attention. This article begins by outlining how the technology–mathematics relationship has developed, from the use of simple aide-mémoires for counting and arithmetic, via the use of mathematics in weaving, building and other trades, and the introduction of calculus to solve technological problems, to the modern use of computers to solve both technological and mathematical problems. Three important philosophical issues emerge from this historical résumé: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Filter spaces and continuous functionals.J. M. E. Hyland - 1979 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 16 (2):101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Practical Intractability: A Critique of the Hypercomputation Movement. [REVIEW]Aran Nayebi - 2014 - Minds and Machines 24 (3):275-305.
    For over a decade, the hypercomputation movement has produced computational models that in theory solve the algorithmically unsolvable, but they are not physically realizable according to currently accepted physical theories. While opponents to the hypercomputation movement provide arguments against the physical realizability of specific models in order to demonstrate this, these arguments lack the generality to be a satisfactory justification against the construction of any information-processing machine that computes beyond the universal Turing machine. To this end, I present a more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The broad conception of computation.Jack Copeland - 1997 - American Behavioral Scientist 40 (6):690-716.
    A myth has arisen concerning Turing's paper of 1936, namely that Turing set forth a fundamental principle concerning the limits of what can be computed by machine - a myth that has passed into cognitive science and the philosophy of mind, to wide and pernicious effect. This supposed principle, sometimes incorrectly termed the 'Church-Turing thesis', is the claim that the class of functions that can be computed by machines is identical to the class of functions that can be computed by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Beyond the universal Turing machine.B. Jack Copeland & Richard Sylvan - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (1):46-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Is Turing's Thesis the Consequence of a More General Physical Principle?Matthew P. Szudzik - 2012 - In S. Barry Cooper (ed.), How the World Computes. pp. 714--722.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hypercomputation.B. Jack Copeland - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (4):461-502.
    A survey of the field of hypercomputation, including discussion of a variety of objections.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • A computable ordinary differential equation which possesses no computable solution.Marian Boylan Pour-el - 1979 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 17 (1):61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Turing's O-machines, Searle, Penrose and the brain.B. J. Copeland - 1998 - Analysis 58 (2):128-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Fast quantum algorithms for handling probabilistic and interval uncertainty.Vladik Kreinovich & Luc Longpré - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (4-5):405-416.
    In many real-life situations, we are interested in the value of a physical quantity y that is difficult or impossible to measure directly. To estimate y, we find some easier-to-measure quantities x1, … , xn which are related to y by a known relation y = f. Measurements are never 100% accurate; hence, the measured values equation image are different from xi, and the resulting estimate equation image is different from the desired value y = f. How different can it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Filter spaces and continuous functionals.J. M. E. Hyland - 1979 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 16 (2):101-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Set theory and physics.K. Svozil - 1995 - Foundations of Physics 25 (11):1541-1560.
    Inasmuch as physical theories are formalizable, set theory provides a framework for theoretical physics. Four speculations about the relevance of set theoretical modeling for physics are presented: the role of transcendental set theory (i) in chaos theory, (ii) for paradoxical decompositions of solid three-dimensional objects, (iii) in the theory of effective computability (Church-Turing thesis) related to the possible “solution of supertasks,” and (iv) for weak solutions. Several approaches to set theory and their advantages and disadvatages for physical applications are discussed: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • 2010 North American Annual Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.Reed Solomon - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):127-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Incompleteness of Axiomatized Models for the Empirical Sciences.Newton C. A. da Costa & Francisco Antonio Doria - 1992 - Philosophica 50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations