Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Numbers, properties, and Frege.Brendan P. Minogue - 1977 - Philosophical Studies 31 (6):423 - 427.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Fregean One-to-one Correspondence and Numbers as Object Properties.Boris Grozdanoff - 2009 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 13 (3):327-338.
    The paper critically examines an unpopular line of Frege’s view on numbers in the Foundations of Arithmetic. According to this view, which analyzes numbers in terms of properties and not in terms of extensions, numbers are properties of concepts vs. properties of objects. The latter view is held by Mill and is famously criticized in the Foundations. I argue that on the property account numbers cannot only be properties of concepts but they also have to be properties of objects. My (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The One and The Many: Aristotle on The Individuation of Numbers.S. Gaukroger - 1982 - Classical Quarterly 32 (02):312-.
    In Book K of the Metaphysics Aristotle raises a problem about a very persistent concern of Greek philosophy, that of the relation between the one and the many , but in a rather peculiar context. He asks: ‘What on earth is it in virtùe of which mathematical magnitudes are one? It is reasonable that things around us [i.e. sensible things] be one in virtue of [their] ψνχ or part of their ψνχ, or something else; otherwise there is not one but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Explicit Abstract Objects in Predicative Settings.Sean Ebels-Duggan & Francesca Boccuni - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 53 (5):1347-1382.
    Abstractionist programs in the philosophy of mathematics have focused on abstraction principles, taken as implicit definitions of the objects in the range of their operators. In second-order logic (SOL) with predicative comprehension, such principles are consistent but also (individually) mathematically weak. This paper, inspired by the work of Boolos (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87, 137–151, 1986) and Zalta (Abstract Objects, vol. 160 of Synthese Library, 1983), examines explicit definitions of abstract objects. These axioms state that there is a unique (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Multiple reductions revisited.Justin Clarke-Doane - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (2):244-255.
    Paul Benacerraf's argument from multiple reductions consists of a general argument against realism about the natural numbers (the view that numbers are objects), and a limited argument against reductionism about them (the view that numbers are identical with prima facie distinct entities). There is a widely recognized and severe difficulty with the former argument, but no comparably recognized such difficulty with the latter. Even so, reductionism in mathematics continues to thrive. In this paper I develop a difficulty for Benacerraf's argument (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Rules to Infinity: The Normative Role of Mathematics in Scientific Explanation.Mark Povich - 2024 - Oxford University Press USA.
    One central aim of science is to provide explanations of natural phenomena. What role(s) does mathematics play in achieving this aim? How does mathematics contribute to the explanatory power of science? Rules to Infinity defends the thesis, common though perhaps inchoate among many members of the Vienna Circle, that mathematics contributes to the explanatory power of science by expressing conceptual rules, rules which allow the transformation of empirical descriptions. Mathematics should not be thought of as describing, in any substantive sense, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark