Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The False Dichotomy: Do “Everything” or Give Up.Jonna D. Clark & Denise M. Dudzinski - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):26-27.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 26-27, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Making a Fetish of “CPR” Is Not in the Patient's Best Interest.John J. Paris & M. Patrick Moore Jr - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (2):37-39.
    Rosoff and Schneiderman's essay “Irrational Exuberance: Cardiopulmonary Resuscitation as Fetish” (2017) raises an issue first posed by the then Chairman of the Federal Reserve Board, Alan Greenspan...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Truth and Communication in Ethics Consultation.George J. Agich - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):31-33.
    In “Deception and the Clinical Ethicist,” Christopher Meyers defends that view that deception practiced by clinical ethicists is legitimate if it satisfies a series of justifying conditions (Meyers...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Deception and the Clinical Ethicist.Christopher Meyers - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):4-12.
    Lying to one’s patients is wrong. So obvious as to border on a platitude, this truism is one that bioethicists have heartily endorsed for several decades. Deception, the standard line holds, underc...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Ethics of crisis sedation: questions of performance and consent.Nathan Emmerich & Bert Gordijn - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (5):339-345.
    This paper focuses on the practice of injecting patients who are dying with a relatively high dose of sedatives in response to a catastrophic event that will shortly precipitate death, something that we term ‘crisis sedation.’ We first present a confabulated case that illustrates the kind of events we have in mind, before offering a more detailed account of the practice. We then comment on some of the ethical issues that crisis sedation might raise. We identify the primary value of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lies, Damned Lies, and Bioethicists.Brian M. Cummings & John J. Paris - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):24-26.
    The opening sentence of Christopher Meyers’ Target Article is “Lying to one’s patient is wrong”. The author continues, “This truism is one that bioethicists have heartedly endorsed fo...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • After the DNR: Surrogates Who Persist in Requesting Cardiopulmonary Resuscitation.Ellen M. Robinson, Wendy Cadge, Angelika A. Zollfrank, M. Cornelia Cremens & Andrew M. Courtwright - 2017 - Hastings Center Report 47 (1):10-19.
    Some health care organizations allow physicians to withhold cardiopulmonary resuscitation from a patient, despite patient or surrogate requests that it be provided, when they believe it will be more harmful than beneficial. Such cases usually involve patients with terminal diagnoses whose medical teams argue that aggressive treatments are medically inappropriate or likely to be harmful. Although there is state-to-state variability and a considerable judicial gray area about the conditions and mechanisms for refusals to perform CPR, medical teams typically follow a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Justifying Clinical Deception: Some Amendments to Brummett and Salter.Christopher Meyers - 2023 - Hastings Center Report 53 (1):26-27.
    In Abram Brummett and Erica K. Salter's excellent paper, “Mapping the Moral Terrain of Clinical Deception,” they rightly note that it is sometimes ethically appropriate for health care professionals to deceive patients and families. However, they also note that because doing so violates a prima facie duty of honesty, the ethical burden of proof falls upon the deceiver. Hence, they also provide a sophisticated framework for determining whether any given case is warranted. I applaud their overall approach but also critique (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parental Permission in the Context of Family-Centered Care.Nate W. Olson - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (11):26-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Informed Non-Dissent: A Better Option Than Slow Codes When Families Cannot Bear to Say “Let Her Die”.Alexander A. Kon - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):22-23.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 22-23, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • “Erring on the Side of Life” Is Sometimes an Error: Physicians Have the Primary Responsibility to Correct This.Arthur R. Derse - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (2):39-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Quick and Limited Is Better Than Slow, Sloppy, or Sly.Wynne Morrison & Chris Feudtner - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):15-16.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 15-16, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mapping the Moral Terrain of Clinical Deception.Abram Brummett & Erica K. Salter - 2023 - Hastings Center Report 53 (1):17-25.
    Legal precedent, professional‐society statements, and even many medical ethicists agree that some situations may call for a clinician to engage in an act of lying or nonlying deception of a patient or patient's family member. Still, the moral terrain of clinical deception is largely uncharted, and when it comes to practical guidance for clinicians, many might think that ethicists offer nothing more than the rule never to deceive. This guidance is insufficient to meet the real‐world demands of clinical practice, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What Is an “Appropriate Code”?Annie Janvier & Keith Barrington - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):18-20.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 18-20, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • In what circumstances will a neonatologist decide a patient is not a resuscitation candidate?Peter Daniel Murray, Denise Esserman & Mark Randolph Mercurio - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (7):429-434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The “Slow Code” Should Be a “No Code”.Ann Weinacker - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):27-29.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 27-29, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Resuscitation of “Slow Codes”: Fraud, Lies, and Deception.John J. Paris & Michael Patrick Moore - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):13-14.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 13-14, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Should the Clinical Ethicist Document Her Complicity in Intentional Deception?Lance K. Stell - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):27-30.
    I trust my lawyer more than I trust my doctor.—Shana Alexander, 1992 [The audience laughed.]1The Hippocratic Oath makes the physician invoke external supervision of her adherence to what she affirm...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Faking It: Unnecessary Deceptions and the Slow Code.Mark R. Mercurio - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):17-18.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 17-18, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Nurses’ Participation in Limited Resuscitation: Gray Areas in End of Life Decision-Making.Felicia Stokes & Rick Zoucha - 2021 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 12 (4):239-252.
    Historically nurses have lacked significant input in end-of-life decision-making, despite being an integral part of care. Nurses experience negative feelings and moral conflict when forced to aggressively deliver care to patients at the EOL. As a result, nurses participate in slow codes, described as a limited resuscitation effort with no intended benefit of patient survival. The purpose of this study was to explore and understand the process nurses followed when making decisions about participation in limited resuscitation. Five core categories emerged (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perceptions of slow codes by nurses working on internal medicine wards.Freda DeKeyser Ganz, Rotem Sharfi, Nehama Kaufman & Sharon Einav - 2019 - Nursing Ethics 26 (6):1734-1743.
    Background: Cardio-pulmonary resuscitation is the default procedure during cardio-pulmonary arrest. If a patient does not want cardio-pulmonary resuscitation, then a do not attempt resuscitation order must be documented. Often, this order is not given; even if thought to be appropriate. This situation can lead to a slow code, defined as an ineffective resuscitation, where all resuscitation procedures are not performed or done slowly. Research objectives: To describe the perceptions of nurses working on internal medicine wards of slow codes, including the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is there a place for CPR and sustained physiological support in brain-dead non-donors?Stephen D. Brown - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (10):679-683.
    This article addresses whether cardiopulmonary resuscitation and sustained physiological support should ever be permitted in individuals who are diagnosed as brain dead and who had held previously expressed moral or religious objections to the currently accepted criteria for such a determination. It contrasts how requests for care would normally be treated in cases involving a brain-dead individual with previously expressed wishes to donate and a similarly diagnosed individual with previously expressed beliefs that did not conform to a brain-based conception of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Let's Do Not Resuscitate Placebo Cardiopulmonary Resuscitation.William Lawrence Allen - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):24-25.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 24-25, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When First We Practice to Deceive.Jason T. Eberl & Erica K. Salter - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):15-17.
    We argue against Christopher Meyers’s call for clinical ethicists to participate in deceiving patients, surrogate decision-makers, or family members. While we acknowledge that some forms of deception may be ethically appropriate in highly circumscribed situations, the type of case Meyers describes as involving justifiable deception differs in at least two important ways. First, Meyers fails to distinguish acts of deception based on the critical feature of who is being deceived—patient, surrogate, or family member—and the overarching duty to respect the autonomy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Misadventures in CPR: Neglecting Nonmaleficent and Advocacy Obligations.Jeffrey T. Berger - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):20-21.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 20-21, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Never a Simple Choice: Claude S. Beck and the Definitional Surplus in Decision-Making About CPR. [REVIEW]Geoffrey Rees, Caitjan Gainty & Daniel Brauner - 2014 - Medicine Studies 4 (1):91-101.
    Each time patients and their families are asked to make a decision about resuscitation, they are also asked to engage the political, social, and cultural concerns that have shaped its history. That history is exemplified in the career of Claude S. Beck, arguably the most influential researcher and teacher of resuscitation in the twentieth century. Careful review of Beck’s work discloses that the development and popularization of the techniques of resuscitation proceeded through a multiplication of definitions of death. CPR consequently (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Not a Transparent Slow Code?Rosalind Ekman Ladd & Edwin N. Forman - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (11):29-30.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 11, Page 29-30, November 2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark