Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Why Truthfulness is the First of the Virtues.Bryan C. Pilkington & Lauris C. Kaldjian - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):36-38.
    Christopher Meyers attempts a utilitarian defense of the deception of patients when the purported harms of truthful disclosure outweigh its benefits. He suggests that honesty i...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Deception and the Clinical Ethicist.Christopher Meyers - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):4-12.
    Lying to one’s patients is wrong. So obvious as to border on a platitude, this truism is one that bioethicists have heartily endorsed for several decades. Deception, the standard line holds, underc...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Falling on One’s Sword for Truth: Deception by Ethicist Should Be Narrow.Joseph P. DeMarco, Toni Nicoletti & Paul J. Ford - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):20-21.
    Clinical ethics consultants should show bold moral courage in discharging their duties to patients, families, and healthcare providers. Given the corrosive impact on trust, and on the appropriate d...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hare’s Archangel, Human Fallibility, and Utilitarian Justification(?) of Deception.William Paul Kabasenche & Thomas May - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):17-19.
    The target article by Christopher Meyers concerning justification of deception for clinical ethicists is both well-reasoned and plausible. Clearly grounded in utilitarian considerations, its...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ethicists’ Deception: Theory, Role, Concepts, and Applications.Christopher Meyers - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):W1-W4.
    I am grateful to colleagues for their comments on my target article ; they are almost uniformly insightful, telling, and helpful. In this brief response, I extend the discussion on, in order...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Exploring Partial Disclosure in Research: Challenges, Justifications, and Recommendations for Ethical Oversight.Ifeanyichukwu Akuma & Vina Vaswani - forthcoming - Asian Bioethics Review:1-21.
    Deception in research is contentious, as ethical codes stress informed consent, yet complete disclosure may jeopardise validity. Indian Council for Medical Research (ICMR) guidelines classify deception into active, incomplete, and authorised forms. This study explores the ethical justification for incomplete (partial disclosure), permissible instances, and the dilemma faced by ethics committees in balancing scientific rigour and participant protection. The qualitative, non-experimental cross-sectional research, using in-depth interviews, identifies themes through thematic analysis. Findings reveal challenges for ethics committees, as incomplete information hampers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lies, Damned Lies, and Bioethicists.Brian M. Cummings & John J. Paris - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):24-26.
    The opening sentence of Christopher Meyers’ Target Article is “Lying to one’s patient is wrong”. The author continues, “This truism is one that bioethicists have heartedly endorsed fo...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Lies of Omission and Commission, Providing and Withholding Treatment, Local and Global Autonomy – There Are Reasons for Clinical Ethicists to Attend to All of These Distinctions.Jonathan Pugh - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):43-45.
    Meyers argues that clinical ethicists should sometimes be active participants in the deception of patients and families, whether that involves lies of omission or commission. I shall...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Robot Technology for the Elderly and the Value of Veracity: Disruptive Technology or Reinvigorating Entrenched Principles?Seppe Segers - 2022 - Science and Engineering Ethics 28 (6):1-14.
    The implementation of care robotics in care settings is identified by some authors as a disruptive innovation, in the sense that it will upend the praxis of care. It is an open ethical question whether this alleged disruption will also have a transformative impact on established ethical concepts and principles. One prevalent worry is that the implementation of care robots will turn deception into a routine component of elderly care, at least to the extent that these robots will function as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Trust, Transparency, and Trauma Informed Care.Elizabeth Lanphier - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):38-40.
    Not only is deception commonplace in medical encounters, according to Christopher Meyers (2021), but the clinical ethicist might have moral obligations to support and even enact deception. Descriptively Meyers is right that there are “opportunistic, self-interested and benevolent reasons” for deception through omission and commission in clinical medicine. But it is possible to retain this premise while rejecting the normative conclusion that the clinical ethicist “should sometimes be an active participant in the deception of patients and families.” One reason to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Justifying Clinical Deception: Some Amendments to Brummett and Salter.Christopher Meyers - 2023 - Hastings Center Report 53 (1):26-27.
    In Abram Brummett and Erica K. Salter's excellent paper, “Mapping the Moral Terrain of Clinical Deception,” they rightly note that it is sometimes ethically appropriate for health care professionals to deceive patients and families. However, they also note that because doing so violates a prima facie duty of honesty, the ethical burden of proof falls upon the deceiver. Hence, they also provide a sophisticated framework for determining whether any given case is warranted. I applaud their overall approach but also critique (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deceptive Omissions, Half-Truths, and the Moral Exemplar in Clinical Ethics.Matthew Kopec - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):33-35.
    In “Deception and the Clinical Ethicist,” Christopher Meyers argues that clinical ethicists sometimes ought to actively help deceive patients or their families, all...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Should the Clinical Ethicist Document Her Complicity in Intentional Deception?Lance K. Stell - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):27-30.
    I trust my lawyer more than I trust my doctor.—Shana Alexander, 1992 [The audience laughed.]1The Hippocratic Oath makes the physician invoke external supervision of her adherence to what she affirm...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nursing ethics as a distinct entity within bioethics: Implications for clinical ethics practice.Bryan Pilkington & Maryanne Giuliante - 2023 - Nursing Ethics 30 (5):671-679.
    The question of whether nursing ethics is a distinct entity within bioethics is an important and thought-provoking one. Though fundamental bioethical principles are appreciated and applied within the practice of nursing ethics, there exist distinct considerations which make nursing ethics a unique subfield of bioethics. In this article, we focus on the importance of relationships as a distinguishing feature of the foundation of nursing ethics, evidenced in its education, practice, and science. Next, we consider two objections to our claim of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truth and Communication in Ethics Consultation.George J. Agich - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):31-33.
    In “Deception and the Clinical Ethicist,” Christopher Meyers defends that view that deception practiced by clinical ethicists is legitimate if it satisfies a series of justifying conditions (Meyers...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Neurofeedback as placebo: a case of unintentional deception?Louiza Kalokairinou, Laura Specker Sullivan & Anna Wexler - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (12):1037-1042.
    The use of placebo in clinical practice has been the topic of extensive debate in the bioethics literature, with much scholarship focusing on concerns regarding deception. While considerations of placebo without deception have largely centred on open-label placebo, this paper considers a different kind of ethical quandary regarding placebo without an intent to deceive—one where the provider believes a treatment is effective due to a direct physiological mechanism, even though that belief may not be supported by rigorous scientific evidence. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Caregivers’ perceptions of compulsory treatment of physical illness in involuntarily psychiatric hospitalization.Sophie Joury, Oren Asman & Azgad Gold - 2023 - Nursing Ethics 30 (3):423-436.
    Background Physical morbidity is rife among patients with serious mental illness. When they are involuntarily hospitalized and even treated, they may still refuse treatment for physical illness leading clinicians to wonder about the ethics of coercing such treatments. Research aim This survey study explored psychiatric caregivers’ perceptions on whether compulsory treatment of physical illness is legal and whether it is justifiable in patients with serious mental illness and under what circumstances. Research design A questionnaire that included two case vignettes of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chinese Clinical Ethicists Accept Physicians’ Benevolent Deception of Patients.Yuming Wang, Zhenxiang Zhang, Hongmei Zhang, Li Tian & Hui Zhang - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):22-24.
    In “Deception and the Clinical Ethicist,” Meyers defends the argument that the clinical ethicist should sometimes be an active participant in the deception of patients and their families. Me...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • When First We Practice to Deceive.Jason T. Eberl & Erica K. Salter - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):15-17.
    We argue against Christopher Meyers’s call for clinical ethicists to participate in deceiving patients, surrogate decision-makers, or family members. While we acknowledge that some forms of deception may be ethically appropriate in highly circumscribed situations, the type of case Meyers describes as involving justifiable deception differs in at least two important ways. First, Meyers fails to distinguish acts of deception based on the critical feature of who is being deceived—patient, surrogate, or family member—and the overarching duty to respect the autonomy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Lying is Not an Option for Clinical Ethics Consultants.Nancy Neveloff Dubler - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):13-15.
    How one reacts to lying depends on individual temperament, intellectual training and value commitments, freedom status,, consideration of consequences, emotional resilience an...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Controversial Analysis of “Deception” Prevents Adequate Moral Analysis.Shlomo Cohen - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):41-42.
    Anyone who is not a deontological absolutist regarding truthfulness will readily agree with Christopher Meyers’s thesis that there are cases in which...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations