Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Stochastic Model of Mathematics and Science.David H. Wolpert & David B. Kinney - 2024 - Foundations of Physics 54 (2):1-67.
    We introduce a framework that can be used to model both mathematics and human reasoning about mathematics. This framework involves stochastic mathematical systems (SMSs), which are stochastic processes that generate pairs of questions and associated answers (with no explicit referents). We use the SMS framework to define normative conditions for mathematical reasoning, by defining a “calibration” relation between a pair of SMSs. The first SMS is the human reasoner, and the second is an “oracle” SMS that can be interpreted as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Certain and Uncertain Inference with Indicative Conditionals.Paul Égré, Lorenzo Rossi & Jan Sprenger - forthcoming - Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
    This paper develops a trivalent semantics for the truth conditions and the probability of the natural language indicative conditional. Our framework rests on trivalent truth conditions first proposed by Cooper (1968) and Belnap (1973) and it yields two logics of conditional reasoning: (i) a logic C of certainty-preserving inference; and (ii) a logic U for uncertain reasoning that preserves the probability of the premises. We show systematic correspondences between trivalent and probabilistic representations of inferences in either framework, and we use (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probabilistic semantics: An overview.Hugues Leblanc - 1980 - Philosophia 9 (2):231-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the logic of nonmonotonic conditionals and conditional probabilities.James Hawthorne - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (2):185-218.
    I will describe the logics of a range of conditionals that behave like conditional probabilities at various levels of probabilistic support. Families of these conditionals will be characterized in terms of the rules that their members obey. I will show that for each conditional, →, in a given family, there is a probabilistic support level r and a conditional probability function P such that, for all sentences C and B, 'C → B' holds just in case P[B | C] ≥ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • On the logic of nonmonotonic conditionals and conditional probabilities: Predicate logic. [REVIEW]James Hawthorne - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (1):1-34.
    In a previous paper I described a range of nonmonotonic conditionals that behave like conditional probability functions at various levels of probabilistic support. These conditionals were defined as semantic relations on an object language for sentential logic. In this paper I extend the most prominent family of these conditionals to a language for predicate logic. My approach to quantifiers is closely related to Hartry Field's probabilistic semantics. Along the way I will show how Field's semantics differs from a substitutional interpretation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Dynamic Formal Epistemology.Patrick Girard, Olivier Roy & Mathieu Marion (eds.) - 2010 - Berlin, Germany: Springer.
    This volume is a collation of original contributions from the key actors of a new trend in the contemporary theory of knowledge and belief, that we call “dynamic epistemology”. It brings the works of these researchers under a single umbrella by highlighting the coherence of their current themes, and by establishing connections between topics that, up until now, have been investigated independently. It also illustrates how the new analytical toolbox unveils questions about the theory of knowledge, belief, preference, action, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Probability functions and their assumption sets — the binary case.Hugues Leblanc & Charles G. Morgan - 1984 - Synthese 60 (1):91 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Logiques et sémantiques non classiques.Alain Voizard - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (1):3-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probabilistic Semantics Objectified: I. Postulates and Logics.Bas C. Van Fraassen - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (3):371-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Probabilistic Semantics, Identity and Belief.William Seager - 1983 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (3):353 - 364.
    The goal of standard semantics is to provide truth conditions for the sentences of a given language. Probabilistic Semantics does not share this aim; it might be said instead, if rather cryptically, that Probabilistic Semantics aims to provide belief conditions.The central and guiding idea of Probabilistic Semantics is that each rational individual has ‘within’ him or her a personal subjective probability function. The output of the function when given a certain sentence as input represents the degree of likelihood which the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hommage à Hugues Leblanc, philosophe logicien.Robert Nadeau - 1986 - Philosophiques 13 (1):131-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Meeting of the association for symbolic logic: Wellington, new zealand, 1981.W. G. Malcolm & M. J. Cresswell - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):519-526.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What price substitutivity? A note on probability theory.Hugues Leblanc - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (2):317-322.
    Teddy Seidenfeld recently claimed that Kolmogorov's probability theory transgresses the Substitutivity Law. Underscoring the seriousness of Seidenfeld's charge, the author shows that (Popper's version of) the law, to wit: If (∀ D)(Pr(B,D)=Pr(C,D)), then Pr(A,B)=Pr(A,C), follows from just C1. 0≤ Pr(A,B)≤ 1 C2. Pr(A,A)=1 C3. Pr(A & B,C)=Pr(A,B & C)× Pr(B,C) C4. Pr(A & B,C)=Pr(B & A,C) C5. Pr(A,B & C)=Pr(A,C & B), five constraints on Pr of the most elementary and most basic sort.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Probability functions and their assumption sets — the singulary case.Hugues Leblanc - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (4):379 - 402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • From worlds to probabilities: A probabilistic semantics for modal logic.Charles B. Cross - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (2):169 - 192.
    I give a probabilistic semantics for modal logic in which modal operators function as quantifiers over Popper functions in probabilistic model sets, thereby generalizing Kripke's semantics for modal logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A “definitive” probabilistic semantics for first-order logic.Kent Bendall - 1982 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (3):255 - 278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark