Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Permanecer en la inversión: una vía no platónica de acceso a la materialidad del pensamiento.Gustavo Bustos Gajardo - 2020 - Endoxa 45:133.
    El objetivo de este ensayo es abrir un conjunto de preguntas en torno a la materialidad del pensamiento, sin que ello signifique, a fin de cuentas, establecer una teoría materialista que actúe en desmedro de las ideas. Tampoco se trata, como observará el lector, de reivindicar una teoría de las ideas contra la materia. Lo que se pretende, considerando una contaminación cruzada entre lo sensible y lo inteligible, es rastrear otra verdad para aquello que ha sido considerado, especialmente por el (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Nature and Normativity: Normativity, Teleology, and Mechanism in Biological Explanation.Lenny Moss & Daniel J. Nicholson - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43 (1):88-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Paley’s design argument as an inference to the best explanation, or, Dawkins’ dilemma.Sander Gliboff - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 31 (4):579-597.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Natura Mayerialiter Spectata Naturaleza, Finalidad y Organismo en la Crítica de la Facultad de Juzgar de KANT.Eduardo Molina Cantó - 2009 - Revista de filosofía (Chile) 65:43-56.
    Uno de los problemas que se le presentan a Kant en la Crítica de la facultad de juzgar es el de la aptitud de la naturaleza en su diversidad particular para ser conformada por las leyes del entendimiento. En este contexto, Kant defi ne los conceptos de naturaleza, materia y fi nalidad de una manera que antes no había tenido cabida en su sistema, y postula la idea de una técnica o arte de la naturaleza. En este artículo se analiza (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alexander von Humboldt, Humboldtian Science and the Origins of the Study of Vegetation.Malcolm Nicolson - 1987 - History of Science 25 (2):167-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Why bioethics cannot figure out what to do with race.Olivette R. Burton - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (2):6 – 12.
    Race and religion are integral parts of bioethics. Harm and oppression, with the aim of social and political control, have been wrought in the name of religion against Blacks and people of color as embodied in the Ten Commandments, the Inquisition, and in the history of the Holy Crusades. Missionaries came armed with Judeo/Christian beliefs went to nations of people of color who had their own belief systems and forced change and caused untold harms because the indigenous belief systems were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Mary Shepherd and the Meaning of ‘Life’.Deborah Boyle - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (2):208-225.
    In the final chapters of her 1824 Essay upon the Relation of Cause and Effect, Lady Mary Shepherd considers what it means for an organism to be alive. The physician William Lawrence had...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Life, Lawfulness, and Contingency: Kant and Schelling on Organic Nature.Naomi Fisher - 2023 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 105 (1):163-188.
    In the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant calls purposiveness the “lawfulness of the contingent”. I argue that this should be interpreted not as lawfulness assumed in order to remove unacceptable mechanical indeterminacy, but rather as an additional kind of lawfulness which, in the case of organisms, inexplicably coincides with mechanical determination. Schelling adapts Kant’s notion of natural purposiveness in his own conception of the relation between mechanism and organism. He states in his 1798 work, On the World Soul, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Kant on epigenesis, monogenesis and human nature: The biological premises of anthropology.Alix A. Cohen - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):675-693.
    The aim of this paper is to show that for Kant, a combination of epigenesis and monogenesis is the condition of possibility of anthropology as he conceives of it and that moreover, this has crucial implications for the biological dimension of his account of human nature. More precisely, I begin by arguing that Kant’s conception of mankind as a natural species is based on two premises: firstly the biological unity of the human species (monogenesis of the human races); and secondly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Quantifying Characters: Polygenist Anthropologists and the Hardening of Heredity. [REVIEW]Brad D. Hume - 2008 - Journal of the History of Biology 41 (1):119 - 158.
    Scholars studying the history of heredity suggest that during the 19th-century biologists and anthropologists viewed characteristics as a collection of blended qualities passed on from the parents. Many argued that those characteristics could be very much affected by environmental circumstances, which scholars call the inheritance of acquired characteristics or "soft" heredity. According to these accounts, Gregor Mendel reconceived heredity - seeing distinct hereditary units that remain unchanged by the environment. This resulted in particular traits that breed true in succeeding generations, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Teleología y epigénesis: una aproximación a los organismos en la Crítica de la Facultad de Juzgar de Kant.Juan Felipe Guevara-Aristizabal & Xóchitl Arteaga-Villamil - 2014 - Metatheoria – Revista de Filosofía E Historia de la Ciencia 5:21--33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Lenoir thesis revisited: Blumenbach and Kant.John H. Zammito - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43 (1):120-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Naturalising purpose: From comparative anatomy to the ‘adventure of reason’.Philippe Huneman - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):649-674.
    Kant’s analysis of the concept of natural purpose in the Critique of judgment captured several features of organisms that he argued warranted making them the objects of a special field of study, in need of a special regulative teleological principle. By showing that organisms have to be conceived as self-organizing wholes, epigenetically built according to the idea of a whole that we must presuppose, Kant accounted for three features of organisms conflated in the biological sciences of the period: adaptation, functionality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Teleology without regrets. The transformation of physiology in Germany: 1790–1847.Timothy Lenoir - 1981 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 12 (4):293-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Kant’s Concept of Organism Revisited: A Framework for a Possible Synthesis between Developmentalism and Adaptationism?Philippe Huneman - 2017 - The Monist 100 (3):373-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Storm and stress anthropology.Karl J. Fink - 1993 - History of the Human Sciences 6 (1):51-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)13 Die Teleologie der organischen Natur (§§ 64–68).Ina Goy - 2018 - In Otfried Höffe (ed.), Immanuel Kant: Kritik der Urteilskraft. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 209-224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Kantian account of mechanical explanation of natural ends in eighteenth and nineteenth century biology.Henk Jochemsen & Wim Beekman - 2022 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 44 (1):1-24.
    The rise of the mechanistic worldview in the seventeenth century had a major impact on views of biological generation. Many seventeenth century naturalists rejected the old animist thesis. However, the alternative view of gradual mechanistic formation in embryology didn’t convince either. How to articulate the peculiarity of life? Researchers in the seventeenth century proposed both “animist” and mechanistic theories of life. In the eighteenth century again a controversy in biology arose regarding the explanation of generation. Some adhered to the view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant and Schelling on Blumenbach’s formative drive.Naomi Fisher - 2021 - Intellectual History Review 31 (3):391-409.
    Blumenbach’s epigenetic theory, particularly his concept of the formative drive, was appropriated by both Kant and Schelling. Kant’s third Critique endorsement of Blumenbach’s formative drive shows him to be close to Schelling’s conception of nature, since it is evidence of his distance from an artifactual conception of teleology. Schelling also draws on this concept of the formative drive, making the structures operative in the formative drive the explanatory ground of all natural forces and processes, thereby supplying the unity between the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Acerca de los esbozos para una teoría filogenética kantiana.Natalia Andrea Lerussi - 2012 - Metatheoria – Revista de Filosofía E Historia de la Ciencia 3:73--92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolution as a Solution: Franco Andrea Bonelli, Lamarck, and the Origin of Man in Early-Nineteenth-Century Italy.Fabio Forgione - 2020 - Journal of the History of Biology 53 (4):521-548.
    Franco Andrea Bonelli, a disciple of Lamarck, was one of the few naturalists who taught and disseminated transformism in Italy in the early nineteenth century. The explanation of the history of life on Earth offered by Lamarck’s theory was at odds with the Genesis narrative, while the issue of man’s place in nature raised heated debates. Bonelli sought to reconcile science and religion through his original interpretation of the variability of species, but he also focused on anthropological subjects. Following Blumenbach’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Reddish, Iron-Rust Color of the Native Americans. Immanuel Kant's Racism in Context.Joris van Gorkom - 2019 - Con-Textos Kantianos 9:154-177.
    In this essay, I discuss Kant’s views on the “American race.” Robert Bernasconi has pointed out that more research on the sources of Kant’s ideas on non-white races is needed in order to have a better understanding of his racism. This essay responds to that call in order to show how Kant contributed to on-going discussions on the causes and meaning of human differences. However, I will also focus on his influence on his contemporaries. The reason for doing so is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant, von Baer und das kausal‐historische Denken in der Biologie.Timothy Lenoir - 1985 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 8 (2):99-114.
    Kant, von Baer, and causal‐historical thinking in biology. In his Kritik der Urteilskraft Kant set forth an analysis of bio‐causality which attempted to unite the best features of teleological and mechanical frameworks of explanation. Kant's analysis suggested that related organic forms must be materially interconnected in the unity of a fundamental plan or morphotype. In the hands of Karl Ernst von Baer these suggestions led to concrete researches and groundbreaking empirical discoveries, including the discovery of the mammalian ovum. Von Baer's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Immanuel Kant: Kritik der Urteilskraft.Otfried Höffe (ed.) - 2018 - Boston: De Gruyter.
    Kant entwickelt in der Kritik der Urteilskraft eine philosophische Ästhetik, eine Theorie der organischen Natur. Die beiden scheinbar heterogenen Gegenstandsbereiche sind durch das Prinzip der reflektierenden Urteilskraft, die Idee der Zweckmäßigkeit, verbunden, die der Mensch sowohl bei der Reflexion über die schönen Gegenstände der Natur und der Kunst als auch bei seiner Erforschung der organischen Natur zugrunde legt. Da sich alle Zwecke zuletzt auf den Endzweck des Menschen als moralisches Wesen beziehen, übersteigt die dritte „Kritik" schließlich die Bereiche von Kunst (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Instruments of Judgment: Inscribing Organic Processes in Late Eighteenth-Century Germany.Joan Steigerwald - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (1):79-131.
    The paper argues for the importance to Kant's critique of judgment of epistemological reflections upon the problematics of experimentation on organic processes. It examines the investigations of generation by Wolff and Blumenbach, demonstrating how their experimental practices mediated reflectively between organic phenomena and their conceptualisation, acting as instruments of their judgments of these processes. It then reads Kant's ‘Kritik der teleologischen Urteilskraft’ in light of these experimental investigations, arguing that Kant highlights how the problematic relation between organic phenomena and their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Nuance Lost in Translation: Interpretations of J. F. Blumenbach’s Anthropology in the English Speaking World.John S. Michael - 2017 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 25 (3):281-309.
    Johann Friedrich Blumenbach has been called ‘The Father of Physical Anthropology’ because of his pioneering publications describing human racial variation. He proposed a racial typology consisting of five ‘major varieties/races’ of humanity. Since the 1990s, Londa Schiebinger and other Anglophone scholars have argued that Blumenbach’s writings on race show evidence that he was significantly influenced by nineteenth-century race supremacist beliefs which held Europeans/caucasians to be the highest ranked and most beautiful race. However, these modern authors relied largely on Thomas Bendyshe’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Kantian Stance on Teleology in Biology.Alix A. Cohen - 2007 - South African Journal of Philosophy 26 (2):109 - 121.
    The aim of this paper is to show firstly why Kant believes we should hang on to teleology, and, secondly, that his views on the matter are still relevant to contemporary epistemology despite the fact that theories of evolution now allow purely mechanical explanations of organic processes. By considering Kant’s account in light of that of Daniel Dennett, I elucidate what I believe to be the strength of Kant’s theory, namely, the pragmatic role it assigns to reflective teleological principles. (edited).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Johann Gottlieb Steeb on Human Diversity: Synthesizing Kant and Blumenbach.Joris van Gorkom - 2019 - Critical Philosophy of Race 7 (2):352-371.
    This article shows that Johann Gottlieb Steeb supported different aspects of Kant's theory of race. Despite the growing research on Kant's racial and biological theory, one finds no mention of Steeb in these interpretations. However, his work is relevant because of his attempt in 1785 to synthesize Kant's preformationist terminology with Blumenbach's epigenetic theory. This article aims at understanding this synthesis. Recent interpreters of Kant presuppose that preformationism excluded epigenesis. But already in 1785 Steeb saw the possibility of integrating Kant's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • German academic science and the mandarin ethos, 1850–1880.Robert Paul - 1984 - British Journal for the History of Science 17 (1):1-29.
    During the nineteenth century an intellectual elite formed in Germany which owed its status primarily to educational qualifications rather than to hereditary rights or wealth. With the ascendency of this elite, which Fritz Ringer has called the German ‘mandarins’, came their acceptance as the spiritual bearers of culture in German life. Politically they controlled the life of the Reichstag and hence were the spokesmen of the nation. As an intellectual elite they fed a diet of German idealistic philosophy to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Uncertain legislator: Georges Cuvier's laws of nature in their intellectual context.Dorinda Outram - 1986 - Journal of the History of Biology 19 (3):323-368.
    We should now be able to come to some general conclusions about the main lines of Cuvier's development as a naturalist after his departure from Normandy. We have seen that Cuvier arrived in Paris aware of the importance of physiology in classification, yet without a fully worked out idea of how such an approach could organize a whole natural order. He was freshly receptive to the ideas of the new physiology developed by Xavier Bichat.Cuvier arrived in a Paris also torn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Clocks to Computers: A Machine-Based “Big Picture” of the History of Modern Science.Frans van Lunteren - 2016 - Isis 107 (4):762-776.
    Over the last few decades there have been several calls for a “big picture” of the history of science. There is a general need for a concise overview of the rise of modern science, with a clear structure allowing for a rough division into periods. This essay proposes such a scheme, one that is both elementary and comprehensive. It focuses on four machines, which can be seen to have mediated between science and society during successive periods of time: the clock, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Introduction.Sebastian Olma & Kostas Koukouzelis - 2007 - Theory, Culture and Society 24 (6):1-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Geography, Race and the Malleability of Man: Karl von Baer and the Problem of Academic Particularism in the Russian Human Sciences.Nathaniel Knight - 2017 - Centaurus 59 (1-2):97-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Soziologie and Lebensanschauung: Two Approaches to Synthesizing ‘Kant’ and ‘Goethe’ in Simmel’s Work.Donald N. Levine - 2012 - Theory, Culture and Society 29 (7-8):26-52.
    Contrary to common perceptions of Simmel’s work as dividing into three stages of Darwinism, Kantianism, and Goethean/Bergsonian Life-Philosophy, consideration of the full scope of the Georg Simmel Gesamtausgabe demonstrates Simmel’s concern with both Kant and Goethe as life-long, just as was his engagement with core principles respectively associated with them: Form and Life. What changed in his mind over time was how those two principles were construed and related. In this view, Simmel’s Soziologie can be read as a treatise on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Vitality rediscovered: theorizing post-Soviet ethnicity in Russian social sciences.Serguei Alex Oushakine - 2007 - Studies in East European Thought 59 (3):171-193.
    Based on materials collected during a fieldwork in Barnaul (Siberia, Russia) in 2001–2004, the article explores two provincial academic discourses that are focused on issues of Russian national identity. Ethnohistories of trauma address Russia’s current problems through the constant re-writing of the country’s past in order to demonstrate the non-Russian character of its national and state institutions. In the second discourse, ethno-vitalism, the struggle over constructing and interpreting the nation’s memory of the past is replaced with a similar struggle over (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark