Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Sympathetic action in the seventeenth century: human and natural.Chris Meyns - 2018 - Philosophical Explorations (1):1-16.
    The category of sympathy marks a number of basic divisions in early modern approaches to action explanations, whether for human agency or for change in the wider natural world. Some authors were critical of using sympathy to explain change. They call such principles “unintelligible” or assume they involve “mysterious” action at a distance. Others, including Margaret Cavendish, Anne Conway, and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, appeal to sympathy to capture natural phenomena, or to supply a backbone to their metaphysics. Here I discuss (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mersenne's critique of Giordano Bruno's conception of the relation between God and the universe: A reappraisal.Miguel A. Granada - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (1):pp. 26-49.
    We re-examine Mersenne's critique of Giordano Bruno concerning the question of the extension of the universe and the plurality of worlds as well as that of universal animation. For this, it is necessary to distinguish, especially in the examination of the first question, the strictly cosmological problem from its metaphysical and theological foundation in which the relation between God and the universe is resolved. Mersenne's critique fundamentally concerns this second side of our problem, according to his conviction that Bruno repeats (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theories of Scientific Method from Plato to Mach.Laurens Laudan - 1968 - History of Science 7 (1):1-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The development of mersenne's optics.Daniele Cozzoli - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (1):pp. 9-25.
    This paper reconstructs the development of Mersenne's reflections concerning optics. I argue that Mersenne's optical writings provide crucial insights into Mersenne's Aristotelianism. I reconstruct Mersenne's attempt of explaining the new ideas on light, which were advanced by Kepler, Descartes and Hobbes within Aristotle's natural philosophy. Mersenne explained Kepler's work on light within the Scholastic tradition. In the 1640s, Mersenne was stimulated by the debate concerning Descartes' theory of light, which he accepted only in 1648. Indeed, Mersenne first explained Descartes' law (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La naturaleza de las entidades matemáticas. Gassendi y Mersenne: objetores de Descartes.Soledad Alejandra Velázquez Zaragoza - 2020 - Dianoia 65 (84):111-133.
    Resumen La naturaleza de las entidades matemáticas ha sido un problema filosófico recurrente en diversas épocas; aquí mostraré que fue una pieza clave en la definición de las posturas ontológicas durante la Modernidad temprana. La piedra de toque para la fundamentación de los conocimientos científicos fue el carácter que se atribuyó a las entidades matemáticas -y, en general, a las entidades abstractas, incluidas las lógicas- en la filosofía natural. Expongo dos posiciones de la Modernidad: la que defendió René Descartes, quien (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Role of Numerical Tables in Galileo and Mersenne.Domenico Bertoloni Meli - 2004 - Perspectives on Science 12 (2):164-190.
    Numerical tables are important objects of study in a range of fields, yet they have been largely ignored by historians of science. This paper contrasts and compares ways in which numerical tables were used by Galileo and Mersenne, especially in the Dialogo and Harmonie Universelle. I argue that Galileo and Mersenne used tables in radically different ways, though rarely to present experimental data. Galileo relied on tables in his work on error theory in day three of the Dialogo and also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the frontlines of the scientific revolution: How mersenne learned to love Galileo.Daniel Garber - 2004 - Perspectives on Science 12 (2):135-163.
    : Marin Mersenne was central to the new mathematical approach to nature in Paris in the 1630s and 1640s. Intellectually, he was one of the most enthusiastic practitioners of that program, and published a number of influential books in those important decades. But Mersenne started his career in a rather different way. In the early 1620s, Mersenne was known in Paris primarily as a writer on religious topics, and a staunch defender of Aristotle against attacks by those who would replace (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Pratique et preuve expérimentale en France au XVIIe siècle. L’émergence d’un modèle coopératif.Christian Licoppe - 1993 - Revue de Synthèse 114 (3-4):383-421.
    Les philosophes naturels du XVIIe siècle accordent une importance croissante aux faits nouveaux et singuliers construits par des démonstrations spectaculaires réalisées devant témoins. Cet essai tente de montrer comment cette évolution s’opère comme une synthèse de deux courants auparavant disjoints, d’un côté la pratique coopérative et informelle, critique sans être véhémente, de savants dont Mersenne constitue un bon exemple dans les années 1630, et de l’autre celle des alchimistes, remettant radicalement en cause les savoirs traditionnels tout en restant viscéralement attachés (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A sabedoria humana de Pierre Charron: a ciência e o exercício cético do espírito forte.Estéfano Luís de Sá Winter - 2013 - Filosofia Do Renascimento E Moderna (Encontro Nacional Anpof).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Le trait d'union musical tiré par mersenne entre encyclopédie et rhétorique académique.Michel Dufour - 2001 - Revue de Synthèse 122 (2-4):577-641.
    This paper is a survey of Father Mersenne’s views about the classification of sciences, its reasons and its practical consequences. Some emphasis is put on the interconnection between Mersenne’s two majors ideas about the practice of science : scientific research is an activity mostly devoted to religious apology and to the edification of the people. This religious concern allows him to resist two of the most influential philosophical streams of his time, scepticism and alchemy, which provide some favorite opponents to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gassendi and l'Affaire Galilée of the Laws of Motion.Paolo Galluzzi - 2000 - Science in Context 13 (3-4):509-545.
    In the lively discussions on Galileo's laws of motion after the Pisan's death, we observe what might be called a new “Galilean affair.” That is, a trial brought against his new science of motion mainly by French and Italian Jesuits with the substantial adherence of M. Mersenne. This new trail was originated by Gassendi's presentation of Galileo's de motu not simply as a perfectly coherent doctrine, but also as a convincing argument in favor of the truth of Copernicanism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Experiments, mathematics, physical causes: How mersenne came to doubt the validity of Galileo's law of free fall.Carla Rita Palmerino - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (1):pp. 50-76.
    In the ten years following the publication of Galileo Galilei's Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche intorno a due nuove scienze , the new science of motion was intensely debated in Italy, France and northern Europe. Although Galileo's theories were interpreted and reworked in a variety of ways, it is possible to identify some crucial issues on which the attention of natural philosophers converged, namely the possibility of complementing Galileo's theory of natural acceleration with a physical explanation of gravity; the legitimacy of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mersenne and Mixed Mathematics.Antoni Malet & Daniele Cozzoli - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (1):1-8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark