Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Abstract Geometry and Its Applications in Quantum Mechanics.Robert Murray Jones - 2020 - Open Journal of Philosophy 10 (4):423-426.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Russellian Analysis of Buddhist Catuskoti.Nicholaos Jones - 2020 - Comparative Philosophy 11 (2):63-89.
    Names name, but there are no individuals who are named by names. This is the key to an elegant and ideologically parsimonious strategy for analyzing the Buddhist catuṣkoṭi. The strategy is ideologically parsimonious, because it appeals to no analytic resources beyond those of standard predicate logic. The strategy is elegant, because it is, in effect, an application of Bertrand Russell's theory of definite descriptions to Buddhist contexts. The strategy imposes some minor adjustments upon Russell's theory. Attention to familiar catuṣkoṭi from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Trespassers and Existential Import.Kai-Yee Wong & Chi-Ho Hung - 2019 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 8 (1):57-62.
    It is a received view of the post-Fregean predicate logic that a universal statement has no existential import and thus does not entail its particular (existential) counterpart. This paper takes issue with the view by discussing the trespasser case, which has widely been employed for supporting the view. The trespasser case in fact involves a shift of context. Properly understood, the case provides no support for the received view but rather suggests that we rethink the ‘quantity view’ of the existential (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arguing about the world’s cardinality: Priority, existence, and metaphysical necessity.Sebastián Briceño - 2018 - Filosofia Unisinos 19 (1).
    Metaphysicians still discuss about the number of things. According to monists, there is one thing, either fundamental (Priority Monism) or exclusionary (Existence Monism). According to pluralists, there are many things, either fundamental (Priority Pluralism) or exclusionary (Existence Pluralism). The claims of cardinality of these views are, presumably, metaphysical claims, which means, presumably, that they are necessarily true, if true at all. In this paper, I unravel a common pattern of some of the main arguments used by the parties involved and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Necessarily Maybe. Quantifiers, Modality and Vagueness.Alessandro Torza - 2015 - In Quantifiers, Quantifiers, and Quantifiers. Themes in Logic, Metaphysics, and Language. (Synthese Library vol. 373). Springer. pp. 367-387.
    Languages involving modalities and languages involving vagueness have each been thoroughly studied. On the other hand, virtually nothing has been said about the interaction of modality and vagueness. This paper aims to start filling that gap. Section 1 is a discussion of various possible sources of vague modality. Section 2 puts forward a model theory for a quantified language with operators for modality and vagueness. The model theory is followed by a discussion of the resulting logic. In Section 3, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • El argumento ontológico y la muerte de la metafísica. Dos visiones complementarias: Kant y Hegel.Hector Ferreiro - 2012 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 57 (3):99-120.
    The core of Kant’s criticism of the ontological argument is the thesis that existence is not a real predicate capable of being added to the concept of an object. The concept of the most perfect or the most real being is a subjective content that is as such completely determined, that is to say, that already has all the determinations that define that concept as such. Therefore, to know if that object also exists in the real world is indispensable that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic, Ontological Neutrality, and the Law of Non-Contradiction.Achille C. Varzi - 2014 - In Elena Ficara (ed.), Contradictions: Logic, History, Actuality. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 53–80.
    Abstract. As a general theory of reasoning—and as a general theory of what holds true under every possible circumstance—logic is supposed to be ontologically neutral. It ought to have nothing to do with questions concerning what there is, or whether there is anything at all. It is for this reason that traditional Aristotelian logic, with its tacit existential presuppositions, was eventually deemed inadequate as a canon of pure logic. And it is for this reason that modern quantification theory, too, with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Concept of Existence: History and Definitions by Leading Philosophers.Raul Corazzon - unknown
    "Philosophical discussion of the notion of existence, or being, has centered on two main problems which have not always been very clearly distinguished. First, there is the problem of what we are to say about the existence of fictitious objects, such as centaurs, dragons, and Pegasus; second, there is the problem of what we are t o say about the existence of abstract objects, such as qualities, relations, and numbers. Both problems have tempted philosophers to say that there are inferior (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Denotationless terms and predicates expressive of positive qualities.Rolf A. Eberle - 1969 - Theoria 35 (2):104-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dialogues as a dynamic framework for logic.Helge Rückert - unknown
    Dialogical logic is a game-theoretical approach to logic. Logic is studied with the help of certain games, which can be thought of as idealized argumentations. Two players, the Proponent, who puts forward the initial thesis and tries to defend it, and the Opponent, who tries to attack the Proponent’s thesis, alternately utter argumentative moves according to certain rules. For a long time the dialogical approach had been worked out only for classical and intuitionistic logic. The seven papers of this dissertation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Names.Sam Cumming - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Nonexistent objects.Maria Reicher - 2019 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Are there nonexistent objects, i.e., objects that do not exist? Some examples often cited are: Zeus, Pegasus, Sherlock Holmes, Vulcan (the hypothetical planet postulated by the 19th century astronomer Le Verrier), the perpetual motion machine, the golden mountain, the fountain of youth, the round square, etc. Some important philosophers have thought that the very concept of a nonexistent object is contradictory (Hume) or logically ill-formed (Kant, Frege), while others (Leibniz, Meinong, the Russell of Principles of Mathematics) have embraced it wholeheartedly. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • A model-theoretic criterion of ontology.John Bacon - 1987 - Synthese 71 (1):1 - 18.
    My aim has been to adapt Quine's criterion of the ontological commitment of theories couched in standard quantificational idiom to a much broader class of theories by focusing on the set-theoretic structure of the models of those theories. For standard first-order theories, the two criteria coincide on simple entities. Divergences appear as they are applied to higher-order theories and as composite entities are taken into account. In support of the extended criterion, I appeal to its fruits in treating the various (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the logic of the ontological argument.Paul E. Oppenheimer & Edward N. Zalta - 1991 - Philosophical Perspectives 5:509-529.
    In this paper, the authors show that there is a reading of St. Anselm's ontological argument in Proslogium II that is logically valid (the premises entail the conclusion). This reading takes Anselm's use of the definite description "that than which nothing greater can be conceived" seriously. Consider a first-order language and logic in which definite descriptions are genuine terms, and in which the quantified sentence "there is an x such that..." does not imply "x exists". Then, using an ordinary logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Two Interpretations of “According to a Story”.Maria E. Reicher - 2006 - In Andrea Bottani & Richard Davies (eds.), Modes of Existence: Papers in Ontology and Philosophical Logic. Ontos Verlag. pp. 153-172.
    The general topic of this paper is the ontological commitment to so-called "fictitious objects", that is, things and characters of fictional stories, like Sherlock Holmes and Pegasus. Discourse about fiction seems to entail an ontological commitment to fictitious entities, a commitment that is often deemed inconsistent with empirical facts. For instance, "Pegasus is a flying horse" seems to entail "There are flying horses" as well as "Pegasus exists" (according to some widely accepted logical principles). I discuss two solutions that have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Symmetry and Hybrid Contingentism.Maegan Fairchild - 2024 - In Peter Fritz & Nicholas K. Jones (eds.), Higher-Order Metaphysics. Oxford University Press.
    This paper outlines a defense of hybrid contingentism: that it is contingent which individuals there are, but not contingent what properties there are. Critics pursue two main lines of complaint. First, that the hybrid contingentist’s treatment of haecceitistic properties is metaphysically mysterious, and second, that hybrid contingentism involves an unjustified asymmetry in the associated modal logic. I suggest that these complaints may be too quick, at least in the setting of higher-order metaphysics. It is not at all obvious whether and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Goodness, availability, and argument structure.Anna-Sara Malmgren - 2021 - Synthese 198:10395-10427.
    According to a widely shared generic conception of inferential justification—‘the standard conception’—an agent is inferentially justified in believing that p only if she has antecedently justified beliefs in all the non-redundant premises of a good argument for p. This conception tends to serve as the starting-point in contemporary debates about the nature and scope of inferential justification: as neutral common ground between various competing, more specific, conceptions. But it’s a deeply problematic starting-point. This paper explores three questions that haven’t been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quines ontologiekriterium.Peter Hinst - 1983 - Erkenntnis 19 (1-3):193 - 215.
    This paper consists of two parts. Part I contains a precise model-theoretic reconstruction of Quine's criterion for the ontological presuppositions of a theory. Two versions (K1), (K2) of the criterion are elaborated, (K2) being the more adequate one which is shown through a number of theorems for each version. Part II contains a critical discussion of (K2), in particular of the question wether (K2) is a criterion for ontological presuppositions, i.e. for entities existing independently of the theory. Its answer depends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Prefacing (⊇ X) A ⊃ A (Y/X) WITH (⊇ Y) — A Free Quantification Theory Without Identity.H. Leblanc & R. K. Meyer - 1970 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 16 (8):447-462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Truth values, neither-true-nor-false, and supervaluations.Nuel Belnap - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (3):305 - 334.
    The first section (§1) of this essay defends reliance on truth values against those who, on nominalistic grounds, would uniformly substitute a truth predicate. I rehearse some practical, Carnapian advantages of working with truth values in logic. In the second section (§2), after introducing the key idea of auxiliary parameters (§2.1), I look at several cases in which logics involve, as part of their semantics, an extra auxiliary parameter to which truth is relativized, a parameter that caters to special kinds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Completeness of Free Logic.B. C. van Fraassen - 1966 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 12 (1):219-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Free quantification and logical invariance.G. Aldo Antonelli - 2007 - Rivista di Estetica 33 (1):61-73.
    Henry Leonard and Karel Lambert first introduced so-called presupposition-free (or just simply: free) logics in the 1950’s in order to provide a logical framework allowing for non-denoting singular terms (be they descriptions or constants) such as “the largest prime” or “Pegasus” (see Leonard [1956] and Lambert [1960]). Of course, ever since Russell’s paradigmatic treatment of definite descriptions (Russell [1905]), philosophers have had a way to deal with such terms. A sentence such as “the..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Definitions of “existence”.Nicholas Rescher - 1957 - Philosophical Studies 8 (5):65-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A note on Barker's discussion of Popper's theory of corroboration.W. W. Bartley - 1961 - Philosophical Studies 12 (1-2):5 - 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ontological proof of the devil.Robert J. Richman - 1958 - Philosophical Studies 9 (4):63 - 64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reasoning about partial functions with the aid of a computer.William M. Farmer - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (3):279 - 294.
    Partial functions are ubiquitous in both mathematics and computer science. Therefore, it is imperative that the underlying logical formalism for a general-purpose mechanized mathematics system provide strong support for reasoning about partial functions. Unfortunately, the common logical formalisms — first-order logic, type theory, and set theory — are usually only adequate for reasoning about partial functionsin theory. However, the approach to partial functions traditionally employed by mathematicians is quite adequatein practice. This paper shows how the traditional approach to partial functions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Atomic ontology.Andrew Parisi - 2020 - Synthese 197 (1):355-379.
    The aim of this article is to offer a method for determining the ontological commitments of a formalized theory. The second section shows that determining the consequence relation of a language model-theoretically entails that the ontology of a theory is tied very closely to the variables that feature in that theory. The third section develops an alternative way of determining the ontological commitments of a theory given a proof-theoretic account of the consequence relation for the language that theory is in. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gentzen and Jaśkowski Natural Deduction: Fundamentally Similar but Importantly Different.Allen P. Hazen & Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (6):1103-1142.
    Gentzen’s and Jaśkowski’s formulations of natural deduction are logically equivalent in the normal sense of those words. However, Gentzen’s formulation more straightforwardly lends itself both to a normalization theorem and to a theory of “meaning” for connectives . The present paper investigates cases where Jaskowski’s formulation seems better suited. These cases range from the phenomenology and epistemology of proof construction to the ways to incorporate novel logical connectives into the language. We close with a demonstration of this latter aspect by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Neutral Free Logic: Motivation, Proof Theory and Models.Edi Pavlović & Norbert Gratzl - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (2):519-554.
    Free logics are a family of first-order logics which came about as a result of examining the existence assumptions of classical logic (Hintikka _The Journal of Philosophy_, _56_, 125–137 1959 ; Lambert _Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic_, _8_, 133–144 1967, 1997, 2001 ). What those assumptions are varies, but the central ones are that (i) the domain of interpretation is not empty, (ii) every name denotes exactly one object in the domain and (iii) the quantifiers have existential import. Free (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Algebraic Structures of Mathematical Foundations.Robert Murray Jones - 2020 - Open Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):137-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Robert Goldblatt. Quantifiers, propositions and identity: Admissible semantics for quantified modal and substructural logics. Lecture notes in logic; 38. cambridge: Cambridge university press, 2011. Isbn 978-1-107-01052-9. Pp. XIII + 282. [REVIEW]R. Jones - 2013 - Philosophia Mathematica 21 (1):123-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Free logic.John Nolt - 2021 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Karel Lambert. Free Logic: Selected Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Pp. xii + 191. ISBN 0-521-81816-8. [REVIEW]Graham Priest - 2003 - Philosophia Mathematica 13 (3):326-328.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A definition of truth for theories with intensional definite description operators.Richard E. Grandy - 1972 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (2):137--155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Existence, presupposition and anaphoric space.Andrea Bonomi - 1977 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1):239 - 267.
    The following paper deals with the notion of existence, especially as concerns natural languages. In Section 1, starting from some quite obvious examples drawn from logic, I sketch the problem of the existential presupposition usually ascribed to noun phrases. My opinion is that the point of view frequently adopted in this case is unduly restrictive, for the existence which is believed to be presupposed here is actual existence. Accordingly, I emphasize the need for having a weaker notion of existential presupposition, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logiques et sémantiques non classiques.Alain Voizard - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (1):3-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Notes on “e!”.Karel Lambert - 1958 - Philosophical Studies 9 (4):60 - 63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Existence, the square of opposites, and two-dimensional logic.Ingolf Max - 1994 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 2 (5):135-149.
    Ontological commitments and other problems concerning existence arise in connection with various aspects of logical theories. The semantics of quantification theory is usually formulated in such a manner that theorems are all and only those formulae which come out true under all interpretations in all non-empty domains. There are several approaches to include the empty domain. Paradoxically this apparent semantic extension means surrendering several formulae which are valid and intuitively plausible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jaśkowski’s Universally Free Logic.Ermanno Bencivenga - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (6):1095-1102.
    A universally free logic is a system of quantification theory, with or without identity, whose theses remain logically true if the domain of quantification is empty and some of the singular terms present in the language do not denote existing objects. In the West, logics satisfying and ones satisfying were developed starting in the 1950s. But Stanisław Jaśkowski preceded all this work by some twenty years: his paper “On the Rules of Supposition in Formal Logic” of 1934 can be regarded (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A semantic theory of sortal incorrectness.R. H. Thomason - 1972 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (2):209 - 258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On the Interplay between Logic and Metaphysics.Achille C. Varzi - 2009 - Linguistic and Philosophical Investigations 8:13-36.
    On the one hand, logic has (or ought to have) nothing to do with metaphysics; it ought to have nothing to do with questions concerning what there is, or whether there is anything at all. On the other hand, metaphysics can hardly get off the ground without the help of logical analysis; to be is to be a truth-maker, and the search for truth-makers requires that we lay open the logical structure of our language. So something’s gotta give: either logical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The semantics of singular terms.Gordon Matheson - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (4):439-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Quasi-Truth, Supervaluations and Free Logic.Newton C. A. Da Costa & Otavio Bueno - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):215-226.
    The partial structures approach has two major components: a broad notion of structure (partial structure) and a weak notion of truth (quasi-truth). In this paper, we discuss the relationship between this approach and free logic. We also compare the model-theoretic analysis supplied by partial structures with the method of supervaluations, which was initially introduced as a technique to provide a semantic analysis of free logic. We then combine the three formal frameworks (partial structures, free logic and supervaluations), and apply the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Études sur les règles d'inférence dites règles de Gentzen.Hugues Leblanc - 1963 - Dialogue 1 (4):355-367.
    Je vais traiter ici des inférences dont la validité tient au rôle qu'y jouent les cinq connecteurs « ⊃ », « ∼ », « & », « V » et « ≡ », les deux quantificateurs « ∀ » et « ∃ », et le signe d'identité « = ». Qu'on me permette de rappeler que les deux conjectures présentéd dans ma première étude se sont avéré'es justes. En premier lieu, toute règle de structure et toute règie d'élimination ou d'introduction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Formal results in the logic of existence.Robert Murray Jones - 1964 - Philosophical Studies 15 (1-2):7 - 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fiction, Creation and Fictionality : An Overview.Matthieu Fontaine & Shahid Rahman - 2010 - Methodos 10:1-75.
    La réflexion philosophique sur la non-existence est une thématique qui a été abordée au commencement même de la philosophie et qui suscite, depuis la publication en 1905 de « On Denoting » par Russell, les plus vifs débats en philosophie analytique. Cependant, le débat féroce sur la sémantique des noms propres et des descriptions définies qui surgirent suite à la publication du « On Referring » par Strawson en 1950 n’engagea pas d’étude systématique de la sémantique des fictions. En fait, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Subject and predicate.J. L. Shaw - 1976 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 4 (1-2):155-179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Individuality in Fiction and the Creative Role of the Reader.Matthieu Fontaine & Shahid Rahman - 2012 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 262 (4):539-560.
    The main aim of the paper is to offer a solution compatible with Graham Priest’s Noneism and Amie Thomasson’s Artifactual theory which stresses the epistemic features of the notion of individuality in fiction in a framework where individuals are conceived of as functions (the framework is known as the world-lines-semantics of Hintikka). According to our view, it is the endorsement of a reader’s perspective that extends the range of the values of the functions (individuals) and that offers an alternative solution (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the characterization of entities by means of individuals and properties.Paul Weingartner - 1974 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 3 (3):323 - 336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Notes on “e!”: II.Karel Lambert - 1961 - Philosophical Studies 12 (1-2):1 - 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations