Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Why machines cannot be moral.Robert Sparrow - 2021 - AI and Society (3):685-693.
    The fact that real-world decisions made by artificial intelligences (AI) are often ethically loaded has led a number of authorities to advocate the development of “moral machines”. I argue that the project of building “ethics” “into” machines presupposes a flawed understanding of the nature of ethics. Drawing on the work of the Australian philosopher, Raimond Gaita, I argue that ethical dilemmas are problems for particular people and not (just) problems for everyone who faces a similar situation. Moreover, the force of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Conversion in philosophy: Wittgenstein's "saving word".Antonia Soulez & Melissa McMahon - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    : Wittgenstein raises the notion of "conversion" in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical "grammar," in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries (Freud, James) and from the history of philosophy (Saint Augustine, Descartes).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's “Saving Word”.Antonia Soulez - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of “conversion” in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical “grammar,” in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's "Saving Word".Antonia Soulez & Melissa McMahon - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of "conversion" in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical "grammar," in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's “Saving Word”.Antonia Soulez - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of “conversion” in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical “grammar,” in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's "Saving Word".Antonia Soulez - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of “conversion” in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical “grammar,” in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's "Saving Word".Antonia Soulez - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of “conversion” in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical “grammar,” in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein's Indeterminism.Richard K. Scheer - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (255):5-23.
    Does it follow from Wittgenstein's views about indeterminism that irregularities of nature could take place? Did he believe that chairs could simply disappear and reappear, that water could behave differently than it has, and that a man throwing a fair die might throw ones for a week? Or are these things only imaginable? Is his view simply that if we adopted an indeterministic point of view we would no longer look for causes, or would not always look for causes, because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intentionality as a Conceptually Primitive Relation.Dale Jacquette - 2011 - Acta Analytica 26 (1):15-35.
    If conceptual analysis is possible for finite thinkers, then there must ultimately be a distinction between complex and primitive or irreducible and unanalyzable concepts, by which complex concepts are analyzed as relations among primitive concepts. This investigation considers the advantages of categorizing intentionality as a primitive rather than analyzable concept, in both a historical Brentanian context and in terms of contemporary philosophy of mind. Arguments in support of intentionality as a primitive relation are evaluated relative to objections, especially a recent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations