Switch to: References

Citations of:

Primal Sin

In Gareth B. Matthews (ed.), The Augustinian Tradition. University of California Press (1998)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Free will.Timothy O'Connor & Christopher Evan Franklin - 2018 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    “Free Will” is a philosophical term of art for a particular sort of capacity of rational agents to choose a course of action from among various alternatives. Which sort is the free will sort is what all the fuss is about. (And what a fuss it has been: philosophers have debated this question for over two millenia, and just about every major philosopher has had something to say about it.) Most philosophers suppose that the concept of free will is very (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Koncepcja woli według św. Augustyna – perspektywa antropologiczna.Martyna Koszkało - 2016 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 64 (3):5-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tracing and heavenly freedom.Benjamin Matheson - 2018 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 84 (1):57-69.
    Accounts of heavenly freedom typically attempt to reconcile the claim that the redeemed have free will with the claim that the redeemed cannot sin. In this paper, I first argue that Pawl and Timpe :396–417, 2009) tracing account of heavenly freedom—according to which the redeemed in heaven have only ‘derivative’ free will—is untenable. I then sketch an alternative account of heavenly freedom, one which eschews derivative free will. On this account, the redeemed are able to sin in heaven.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Pride and Preference.William E. Mann - 2006 - Faith and Philosophy 23 (2):156-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Could there be Suffering in Paradise? The Primal Sin, the Beatific Vision, and Suffering in Paradise.David Andrew Worsley - 2016 - Journal of Analytic Theology 4:87-105.
    Paradise is often conceived as a place where suffering is not possible, so much so that the possibility of suffering in paradise has been used by various philosophers as a defeater for the possibility of paradise. [1] Employing a “reverse-engineered-theodicy,” I use Eleonore Stump’s morally-sufficient-reason for why God allows suffering in this earthly world to explore one condition that must obtain for suffering to remain impossible in paradise, namely, that internal fragmentation is not possible in paradise. After developing an intellectualist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Saint Augustine.Michael Mendelson - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy and Christian theology.Michael Murray - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Many of the doctrines central to Christianity have important philosophical implications or presuppositions. In this article, we begin with a brief general discussion of the relationship between philosophy and Christian dogma, and then we turn our attention to three of the most philosophically challenging Christian doctrines: the trinity, the incarnation, and the atonement. We take these three as our focus because, unlike (for example) doctrines about providence or the attributes of God, these are distinctive to Christian theology and, unlike (for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Angelic Sin in Augustine and Anselm.Peter King - unknown
    Augustine and Anselm form a common tradition in mediæval thought about angelic sin, a tradition rooted in patristic thought and centred on their attempts to give a philosophically coherent account of moral choice. Augustine concentrates on the reasons and causes of angelic sin, especially in reference to free will; Anselm adopts Augustine’s analysis and extends it to issues about the rationality of sinful choice. Each takes Lucifer’s primal sin to be the paradigm case. Lucifer, undistracted by bodily desires and unencumbered (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Science, conscience, consciousness.Boris Hennig - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (3):15-28.
    Descartes’ metaphysics lays the foundation for the special sciences, and the notion of consciousness (conscientia) belongs to metaphysics rather than to psychology. I argue that as a metaphysical notion, ‘consciousness’ refers to an epistemic version of moral conscience. As a consequence, the activity on which science is based turns out to be conscientious thought. The consciousness that makes science possible is a double awareness: the awareness of what one is thinking, of what one should be doing, and of the possibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Living Within Our Limits: A Defense of the Fall.Adam Green & Joshua Morris - 2020 - Journal of Analytic Theology 8 (1):371-389.
    In this paper, we use the biology of pain and Augustinian insights into the relationship between physical and spiritual death to give a defense of the Fall. If we think of pain as, biologically, a limiting system but one that interacts with advanced rationality in such a way as to create a new experience of one’s biological limits, then one can use Augustine’s treatment of our experience of physical death as both a consequence and a symbolic check on our moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations