Switch to: References

Citations of:

The provocation to look and see: appropriation, recollection and formal indication

In David Egan, Stephen Reynolds & Aaron Wendland (eds.), Wittgenstein and Heidegger. New York: Routledge (2013)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Toward a Resolute Reading of Being and Time: Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Dilemma between Inconsistency and Ineffability.Gilad Nir - 2021 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 59 (4):572-605.
    Both Heidegger and Wittgenstein consider the possibility of a philosophical inquiry of an absolutely universal scope—an inquiry into the being of all beings, in Heidegger’s case, and into the logical form of everything that can be meaningfully said, in Wittgenstein’s. Moreover, they both raise the worry that the theoretical language by means of which we speak of particular beings and assert particular facts is not suited to this task. And yet their own philosophical work seems to include many assertions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The recent engagement between analytic philosophy and Heideggerian thought: Logic and language.Filippo Casati - 2020 - Philosophy Compass 15 (2):e12651.
    Martin Heidegger's philosophy is famous for being unusually rich. It ranges over technology, poetry, theology, history, and many other subjects. In this paper, I focus my attention on two topics which are particularly close to the hearts of analytic philosophers: logic and language. I show that Heidegger faces two different kinds of paradoxes: an ontic paradox and an ontological paradox. Moreover, for each one of these paradoxes, I give an overview of how both Heidegger and the philosophers who engage with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger and the contradiction of Being: a dialetheic interpretation of the late Heidegger.Filippo Casati - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (5):1002-1024.
    ABSTRACTIt is well known that, from the beginning to the end of his philosophical trajectory, Martin Heidegger tries to develop a fundamental ontology which aims at answering the so-called question...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Enactive becoming.Ezequiel A. Di Paolo - 2020 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 20 (5):783-809.
    The enactive approach provides a perspective on human bodies in their organic, sensorimotor, social, and linguistic dimensions, but many fundamental issues still remain unaddressed. A crucial desideratum for a theory of human bodies is that it be able to account for concrete human becoming. In this article I show that enactive theory possesses resources to achieve this goal. Being an existential structure, human becoming is best approached by a series of progressive formal indications. I discuss three standpoints on human becoming (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Being‐Towards‐Death and Owning One's Judgment.Denis McManus - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (2):245-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Following the Movement of a Showing.James Gilbert-Walsh - 2024 - Angelaki 29 (5):3-19.
    Heidegger qualifies his work with the surprising assertion “I have no philosophy at all.” In this paper, I argue that, to make sense of this odd claim, we must carefully investigate his reflections on philosophical showing. While Heidegger never finished the segment of Being and Time intended to address this issue explicitly, the clues he offers in the published portion of the text indicate that, for him, successful philosophical showing takes place not primarily through a coherent collection of philosophical assertions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beholdenness to Entities and the Concept of ‘Dasein’: Phenomenology, Ontology and Idealism in the early Heidegger.Denis McManus - 2017 - European Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):512-534.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations