Switch to: References

Citations of:

What the doctor didn't say: the hidden truth about medical research

New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Edward P. Richards (2006)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. How Payment For Research Participation Can Be Coercive.Joseph Millum & Michael Garnett - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (9):21-31.
    The idea that payment for research participation can be coercive appears widespread among research ethics committee members, researchers, and regulatory bodies. Yet analysis of the concept of coercion by philosophers and bioethicists has mostly concluded that payment does not coerce, because coercion necessarily involves threats, not offers. In this article we aim to resolve this disagreement by distinguishing between two distinct but overlapping concepts of coercion. Consent-undermining coercion marks out certain actions as impermissible and certain agreements as unenforceable. By contrast, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Is it Really All about the Money? Reconsidering Non-Financial Interests in Medical Research.Richard S. Saver - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):467-481.
    Conflicts of interest have been reduced to financial conflicts. The National Institutes of Health’s new rules for managing conflicts of interest in medical research, the first major change to the regulations in over 15 years, address only financial ties. Although several commentators urged that the regulations also cover non-financial interests, the Department of Health and Human Services declined to do so. Similarly, the Institute of Medicine’s influential 2009 Conflict of Interest Report focuses almost exclusively on financial conflicts. Institutional policies at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reconceptualising the Doctor–Patient Relationship: Recognising the Role of Trust in Contemporary Health Care.Zara J. Bending - 2015 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 12 (2):189-202.
    The conception of the doctor–patient relationship under Australian law has followed British common law tradition whereby the relationship is founded in a contractual exchange. By contrast, this article presents a rationale and framework for an alternative model—a “Trust Model”—for implementation into law to more accurately reflect the contemporary therapeutic dynamic. The framework has four elements: an assumption that professional conflicts with patient safety, motivated by financial or personal interests, should be avoided; an onus on doctors to disclose these conflicts; a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • For the Common Good: Philosophical Foundations of Research Ethics.Alex John London - 2021 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
    The foundations of research ethics are riven with fault lines emanating from a fear that if research is too closely connected to weighty social purposes an imperative to advance the common good through research will justify abrogating the rights and welfare of study participants. The result is an impoverished conception of the nature of research, an incomplete focus on actors who bear important moral responsibilities, and a system of ethics and oversight highly attuned to the dangers of research but largely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Informed Consent, Understanding, and Trust.David B. Resnik - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):61-63.
    Valid Informed consent to medical treatment or research participation has traditionally been viewed as consisting of the following requirements: the person has t...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Limits on risks for healthy volunteers in biomedical research.David B. Resnik - 2012 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 33 (2):137-149.
    Healthy volunteers in biomedical research often face significant risks in studies that offer them no medical benefits. The U.S. federal research regulations and laws adopted by other countries place no limits on the risks that these participants face. In this essay, I argue that there should be some limits on the risks for biomedical research involving healthy volunteers. Limits on risk are necessary to protect human participants, institutions, and the scientific community from harm. With the exception of self-experimentation, limits on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reviews in Medical Ethics.Ana S. Iltis - 2008 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (2):419-424.
    What the Doctor Didn’t Say, by Jerry Menikoff and Edward P. Richards, is a courageous and well-written volume that examines some of the fundamental debates pertaining to the ethics of clinical research. The volume deserves a careful reading by anyone with a potential role in clinical research: clinicians who might serve as investigators or refer patients to clinical trials; research staff; Institutional Review Board members and administrators; sponsors who design clinical trials; and the book’s intended audience, namely, potential research participants (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In Plain Sight: A Solution to a Fundamental Challenge in Human Research.Lois Shepherd & Margaret Foster Riley - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (4):970-989.
    The physician-researcher conflict of interest, a long-standing and widely recognized ethical challenge of clinical research, has thus far eluded satisfactory solution. The conflict is fairly straightforward. Medical research and medical therapy are distinct pursuits; the former is aimed at producing generalizable knowledge for the benefit of future patients, whereas the latter is aimed at addressing the individualized medical needs of a particular patient. When the physician-researcher combines these pursuits, he or she serves two masters and cannot — no matter how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Should We Be Alarmed by Medical Research?Tomas Bogardus - 2008 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 33 (5):524-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Eschewing Definitions of the Therapeutic Misconception: A Family Resemblance Analysis.D. S. Goldberg - 2011 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36 (3):296-320.
    Twenty-five years after the term "therapeutic misconception’ (TM) first entered the literature, most commentators agree that it remains widespread. However, the majority of scholarly attention has focused on the reasons why a patient cum human subject might confuse the goals of research with the goals of therapy. Although this paper addresses the social and cultural factors that seem to animate the TM among subjects, it also fills a niche in the literature by examining why investigators too might operate under a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Overinterpreting Equipoise.Jerry Menikoff - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (2):13 - 14.
    The factual premise: A clinical trial takes place, with results suggesting that a new treatment is better than standard care for a particular medical problem. One large group of physicians—call the...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavior Equipoise: Is It Ready for Prime Time?Katherine Wasson - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (2):14 - 16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When Does Nudging Represent Fraudulent Disclosure?Jennifer Blumenthal-Barby, Neal W. Dickert & Derek Soled - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):63-66.
    In the article “Informed Consent: What Must be Disclosed and What Must be Understood?” Joseph Millum and Danielle Bromwich argue that informed consent requires satisfaction of certain disclosure an...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Vulnerability of the Very Sick.Jerry Menikoff - 2009 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (1):51-58.
    Suppose that someone has a serious illness. The illness will likely lead to significant disabilities, and may even cause death. Existing treatments are unsatisfactory. The patient learns about a clinical trial, in which some allegedly promising new treatment for that illness is being tested.Such seriously ill patients for whom existing treatments are unsatisfactory have sometimes been categorized as medically vulnerable in the literature. Should these patients indeed be considered vulnerable subjects and be provided with special protections? And if the answer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Data and Safety Monitoring Boards: Some Enduring Questions.Charles J. Kowalski & Jan L. Hewett - 2009 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (3):496-506.
    Data Safety and Monitoring Boards were introduced in the 1960s to monitor data in clinical trials to ensure subject safety. It was thought important that DSMB members be experts in the field of interest, but not otherwise involved in the study in order to maximize objectivity. Since then, the use of DSMBs has increased dramatically, and their scope has expanded to include scientific issues — in particular, to avoid bias that can result when trials are stopped early because of evidence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Both Sides of the Coin: Randomization from the Perspectives of Physician-Investigators and Patient-Subjects.Eric D. Kodish, Kathleen A. Kassimatis & Tsiao Yi Yap - 2010 - Ethics and Behavior 20 (5):380-386.
    Randomization is the “gold standard” design for clinical research trials and is accepted as the best way to reduce bias. Although some controversy remains over this matter, we believe equipoise is the fundamental ethical requirement for conducting a randomized clinical trial. Despite much attention to the ethics of randomization, the moral psychology of this study design has not been explored. This article analyzes the ethical tensions that arise from conducting these studies and examines the moral psychology of this design from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations