Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Kant on Spatial Orientation.Sven Bernecker - 2010 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (4):519-533.
    This paper develops a novel interpretation of Kant's argument from incongruent counterparts to the effect that the representations of space and time are intuitions rather than concepts. When properly understood, the argument anticipates the contemporary position whereby the meaning of indexicals cannot be captured by descriptive contents.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Metaphysik im “Handumdrehen” – Kant und Earman, Parität und moderne Raumauffassung.Holger Lyre - 2005 - Philosophia Naturalis 42 (1):49-76.
    In 1768 Immanuel Kant presented an argument showing the necessity of absolute space, i.e. substantivalism in contrast to relationalism, based on the property of handedness. While there is large consensus about the fallacy of Kant’s argument, a more recent debate exists – mainly stimulated by John Earman – about the status of the Kantian argument in view of modern physics and its fundamentally built-in parity violation, which leads to a preferred handedness. According to Earman the relationalist has no means to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The aims and method of Kant's 1768 Gegenden im Raume essay in the light of Euler's 1748 Reflexions sur l'espace.David Walford - 1999 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (2):305 – 332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Urbild und Abbild. Leibniz, Kant und Hausdorff über das Raumproblem.Marco Giovanelli - 2010 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 41 (2):283-313.
    The article attempts to reconsider the relationship between Leibniz’s and Kant’s philosophy of geometry on the one hand and the nineteenth century debate on the foundation of geometry on the other. The author argues that the examples used by Leibniz and Kant to explain the peculiarity of the geometrical way of thinking are actually special cases of what the Jewish-German mathematician Felix Hausdorff called “transformation principle”, the very same principle that thinkers such as Helmholtz or Poincaré applied in a more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Von der Ontologie des Raums zur Ontologie der Raumzeit.Niko Strobach - 2006 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 9 (1):105-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Las contrapartidas incongruentes y el cuerpo propio en el idealismo trascendental de Kant.Matías Hernán Oroño - 2017 - Ideas Y Valores 66 (163):153-176.
    Se defiende la tesis de que la teoría kantiana del espacio, en el contexto del idealis-mo trascendental, constituye un marco adecuado para solucionar la paradoja de las contrapartidas incongruentes. Se incluyen dos hipótesis: a) la solución kantiana implica una referencia a la conciencia de la propia corporalidad, para comprender cómo poseemos la capacidad para orientarnos en el espacio; b) no existe contradicción en el uso kantiano de las contrapartidas incongruentes en diferentes estadios de su pensamiento. La solución kantiana de 1768 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Incongruent counterparts and one's own body in kant's transcendental idealism.Matías Hernán Oroño - 2017 - Ideas Y Valores 66 (163):153-176.
    RESUMEN Se defiende la tesis de que la teoría kantiana del espacio, en el contexto del idealismo trascendental, constituye un marco adecuado para solucionar la paradoja de las contrapartidas incongruentes. Se incluyen dos hipótesis: a) la solución kantiana implica una referencia a la conciencia de la propia corporalidad, para comprender cómo poseemos la capacidad para orientarnos en el espacio; b) no existe contradicción en el uso kantiano de las contrapartidas incongruentes en diferentes estadios de su pensamiento. La solución kantiana de (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A puzzle about incongruent counterparts and the critique of pure reason.Rogério Passos Severo - 2007 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (4):507–521.
    Kant uses incongruent counterparts in his work before and after 1781, but not in the first Critique. Given the relevance that incongruent counterparts had for his thought on space, and their persistence in his work during the 1780s, it is plausible to think that he had a reason for leaving them out of both editions of the Critique. Two implausible conjectures for their absence are here considered and rejected. A more plausible alternative is put forth, which explains that textual absence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation