Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. What we would (but shouldn't) do for those we love: Universalism versus partiality in responding to others' moral transgressions.Laura K. Soter, Martha K. Berg, Susan A. Gelman & Ethan Kross - 2021 - Cognition 217 (C):104886.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How Good Are We At Evaluating Communicated Information?Hugo Mercier - 2021 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 89:257-272.
    Are we gullible? Can we be easily influenced by what others tell us, even if they do not deserve our trust? Many strands of research, from social psychology to cultural evolution suggest that humans are by nature conformist and eager to follow prestigious leaders. By contrast, an evolutionary perspective suggests that humans should be vigilant towards communicated information, so as not to be misled too often. Work in experimental psychology shows that humans are equipped with sophisticated mechanisms that allow them (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Love Redirected: On Adam Smith's Love of Praiseworthiness.Sveinung Sundfør Sivertsen - 2017 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 15 (1):101-123.
    Why be moral? Why, in the language of Adam Smith, act on what you think is praiseworthy even when it does not get you praise from other people? Because, answers Smith, you love praiseworthiness. But what is this love of praiseworthiness, and where does it come from? In this article, 1) I argue that we start to love praiseworthiness when we redirect our love of praise away from other people toward the ‘impartial spectator’-aspect of ourselves, and 2) show how this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Feasibility of Folk Science.Frank C. Keil - 2010 - Cognitive Science 34 (5):826-862.
    If folk science means individuals having well worked out mechanistic theories of the workings of the world, then it is not feasible. Laypeople’s explanatory understandings are remarkably coarse, full of gaps, and often full of inconsistencies. Even worse, most people overestimate their own understandings. Yet recent views suggest that formal scientists may not be so different. In spite of these limitations, science somehow works and its success offers hope for the feasibility of folk science as well. The success of science (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The rise of moral cognition.Joshua D. Greene - 2015 - Cognition 135 (C):39-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Even his friend said he's bad: Children think personal alliances bias gossip.Zoe Liberman & Alex Shaw - 2020 - Cognition 204 (C):104376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Children use disagreement to infer what happened.Jamie Amemiya, Gail D. Heyman & Tobias Gerstenberg - 2024 - Cognition 250 (C):105836.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Children's Sensitivity to Ulterior Motives When Evaluating Prosocial Behavior.Gail Heyman, David Barner, Jennifer Heumann & Lauren Schenck - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (4):683-700.
    Reasoning about ulterior motives was investigated among children ages 6–10 years (total N = 119). In each of two studies, participants were told about children who offered gifts to peers who needed help. Each giver chose to present a gift in either a public setting, which is consistent with having an ulterior motive to enhance one's reputation, or in a private setting, which is not consistent with having an ulterior motive. In each study, the 6- to 7-year olds showed no (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Children recognize and reject favoritism in norm enforcement.Louisa Huff, Tindaya Déniz, Linda Gronem & Sebastian Grueneisen - 2025 - Cognition 254 (C):105981.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark