Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. International Clinical Research and Justice in the Belmont Report.Joseph Millum - 2020 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 63 (2):374-388.
    The Belmont Report was written by a US Commission charged by the US Congress to advise on research supported by the US government. Its focus was understandably domestic. In the 40 years since its publication, clinical research has become increasingly international. Many clinical trials have sites in multiple countries, and many of the host countries are relatively impoverished. Such research raises some distinctive ethical issues. This paper outlines some of the key ethical challenges that have been raised by clinical research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human Rights and Global Mental Health: Reducing the Use of Coercive Measures.Kelso Cratsley, Marisha Wickremsinhe & Timothy K. Mackey - 2021 - In A. Dyer, B. Kohrt & P. J. Candilis (eds.), Global Mental Health: Ethical Principles and Best Practices. pp. 247-268.
    The application of human right frameworks is an increasingly important part of efforts to accelerate progress in global mental health. Much of this has been driven by several influential legal and policy instruments, most notably the United Nations’ Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, as well as the World Health Organization’s QualityRights Tool Kit and Mental Health Action Plan. Despite these significant developments, however, much more needs to be done to prevent human rights violations. This chapter focuses on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lessons in Conflict of Interest: The Construction of the Martyrdom of David Healy and The Dilemma of Bioethics.James Coyne - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):W3-W14.
    Bioethics journals have lagged behind medical and science journals in exploring the threat of conflict of interest (COI) to the integrity of publications. Some recent discussions of COI that have occurred in the bioethics literature are reviewed. Discussions of what has been termed the ?Healy affair? unintentionally demonstrate that the direct and indirect influence of undisclosed COI may come from those who call for protection from the undue influence of industry. Paradoxically, the nature and tone of current discussions may serve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Equipoise and the Ethics of Clinical Research Revisited.Franklin G. Miller - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (4):59-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Neonatal Pain Relief and the Helsinki Declaration.Robert S. Van Howe & J. Steven Svoboda - 2008 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (4):803-823.
    The Helsinki Declaration is the universally accepted standard for ethical behavior in research involving human subjects. The Declaration calls for research studies to compare new therapies to the best current therapies. Despite this standard, multiple studies of pain relief interventions in newborns have recruited placebo controls instead of active controls using the best current therapy. These studies are evaluated using the standards required by the Helsinki Declaration, and the reasons for the ethical shortcomings of these studies are explored.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A renewed, ethical defense of placebo-controlled trials of new treatments for major depression and anxiety disorders.B. W. Dunlop & J. Banja - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (6):384-389.
    The use of placebo as a control condition in clinical trials of major depressive disorder and anxiety disorders continues to be an area of ethical concern. Typically, opponents of placebo controls argue that they violate the beneficent-based, “best proven diagnostic and therapeutic method” that the original Helsinki Declaration of 1964 famously asserted participants are owed. A more consequentialist, oppositional argument is that participants receiving placebo might suffer enormously by being deprived of their usual medication(s). Nevertheless, recent findings of potential for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The clinical investigator-subject relationship: a contextual approach.David B. Resnik - 2009 - Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 4:16-.
    BackgroundThe nature of the relationship between a clinical investigator and a research subject has generated considerable debate because the investigator occupies two distinct roles: clinician and scientist. As a clinician, the investigator has duties to provide the patient with optimal care and undivided loyalty. As a scientist, the investigator has duties to follow the rules, procedures and methods described in the protocol.Results and conclusionIn this article, I present a contextual approach to the investigator-subject relationship. The extent of the investigator's duty (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Subject indifference and the justification of placebo-controlled trials.Robert M. Veatch - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):12 – 13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Clarifying the ethics of clinical research: A path toward avoiding the therapeutic misconception.Paul S. Appelbaum - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):22 – 23.
    (2002). Clarifying the Ethics of Clinical Research: A Path toward Avoiding the Therapeutic Misconception. The American Journal of Bioethics: Vol. 2, No. 2, pp. 22-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • For the Common Good: Philosophical Foundations of Research Ethics.Alex John London - 2021 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
    The foundations of research ethics are riven with fault lines emanating from a fear that if research is too closely connected to weighty social purposes an imperative to advance the common good through research will justify abrogating the rights and welfare of study participants. The result is an impoverished conception of the nature of research, an incomplete focus on actors who bear important moral responsibilities, and a system of ethics and oversight highly attuned to the dangers of research but largely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ethical principles and placebo-controlled trials – interpretation and implementation of the Declaration of Helsinki’s placebo paragraph in medical research.Antonia-Sophie Skierka & Karin B. Michels - 2018 - BMC Medical Ethics 19 (1):24.
    In October 2013, the Declaration of Helsinki was revised a seventh time in its 50 year history. While it is the most widely accepted set of ethical principles for the protection of patients participating in medical research, the Declaration of Helsinki has also been subject of constant controversy. In particular, its paragraph on the use of placebo controls in clinical trials divides the research community into active-control and placebo orthodox proponents, both continuously demanding revisions of the Declaration of Helsinki in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Profitable failure: antidepressant drugs and the triumph of flawed experiments.Linsey McGoey - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (1):58-78.
    Drawing on an analysis of Irving Kirsch and colleagues’ controversial 2008 article in PLoS [Public Library of Science] Medicine on the efficacy of SSRI antidepressant drugs such as Prozac, I examine flaws within the methodologies of randomized controlled trials (RCTs) that have made it difficult for regulators, clinicians and patients to determine the therapeutic value of this class of drug. I then argue, drawing analogies to work by Pierre Bourdieu and Michael Power, that it is the very limitations of RCTs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Equipoise in the Real World.Carmen Paradis - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (4):61-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Contextualizing the Vulnerability Standard.Tricha Shivas - 2004 - American Journal of Bioethics 4 (3):84-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • When "Minimal Risk" Research Yields Clinically-Significant Data, Maybe the Risks Aren't So Minimal.Helen M. Sharp & Robert D. Orr - 2004 - American Journal of Bioethics 4 (2):32-36.
    Surveys and routine clinical procedures applied in research protocols are typically considered only minimally risky to participants. The apparent benign nature of "minimal risk" tasks increases the chance that investigators and Institutional Review Boards (IRBs) will overlook the probability that clinical tools will identify signs, symptoms, or definitive test results that are clinically-relevant to subjects' welfare. "Minimal risk" procedures may also pose a particular hazard to participants in clinical research by increasing the therapeutic misconception because the tasks mimic clinical care (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • “Human Non-Subjects Research”: Privacy and Compliance.Kyle Bertram Brothers & Ellen Wright Clayton - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (9):15-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Unsafe presumptions in clinical research.Rosamond Rhodes - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):49 – 51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rethinking research ethics.Rosamond Rhodes - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):7 – 28.
    Contemporary research ethics policies started with reflection on the atrocities perpetrated upoconcentration camp inmates by Nazi doctors. Apparently, as a consequence of that experience, the policies that now guide human subject research focus on the protection of human subjects by making informed consent the centerpiece of regulatory attention. I take the choice of context for policy design, the initial prioritization of informed consent, and several associated conceptual missteps, to have set research ethics off in the wrong direction. The aim of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Sham surgery in randomized trials: Additional requirements should be satisfied.Howard Mann - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (4):5 – 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Avoiding a jekyll-and-Hyde approach to the ethics of clinical research and practice.Trudo Lemmens & Paul B. Miller - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):14 – 17.
    (2002). Avoiding a Jekyll-And-Hyde Approach to the Ethics of Clinical Research and Practice. The American Journal of Bioethics: Vol. 2, No. 2, pp. 14-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Placebo controls: Scientific and ethical issues.Charles J. Kowalski - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):33 – 34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Distinguishing dilemmas in the ethics of placebo-controlled trials.Karen Kovach - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):32 – 33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exploiting subjects in placebo-controlled trials.Nancy S. Jecker - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):19 – 20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Failure to conduct a placebo-controlled trial may be unethical.Peter J. Cohen - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The real problem with equipoise.Winston Chiong - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (4):37 – 47.
    The equipoise requirement in clinical research demands that, if patients are to be randomly assigned to one of two interventions in a clinical trial, there must be genuine doubt about which is better. This reflects the traditional view that physicians must never knowingly compromise the care of their patients, even for the sake of future patients. Equipoise has proven to be deeply problematic, especially in the Third World. Some recent critics have argued against equipoise on the grounds that clinical research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • What is the best standard for the standard of care in clinical research?Rieke van der Graaf & Johannes J. M. van Delden - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (3):35 – 43.
    During the past decennium, one of the main issues discussed in research ethics has been focused on the care that should be provided to the control group in a clinical trial. This discussion is also called the standard of care debate . Current international research ethics guidelines contain a wide variety of standards for the standard of care—including the provision of the highest attainable, the best available, the best current, a proven , and an established effective treatment. In this article, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Personalizing transcranial direct current stimulation for treating major depressive disorder.Stephan Goerigk - unknown
    Transcranial direct current stimulation is a safe and efficient intervention for treating major depressive disorder. However, research has suggested heterogeneity of response between patients. The emerging field of precision psychiatry aims to use statistical modeling of multi-modal data to tailor treatment to the single patient. To this end, more in-depth analysis of randomized controlled trials will be relevant due to limited availability of other large datasets with high phenotypic detail and to develop tools for personalization within counterfactually controlled environments to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Legal responses to placebo-controlled trials in developing countries.Ilja Richard Pavone - 2016 - Global Bioethics 27 (2-4):76-90.
    The conduct of clinical trials involving placebo in developing countries in the presence of an existing effective treatment triggered an intense debate on the standard of care to be provided to those populations. Charges of exploitation of vulnerable groups and double standards have been raised by several scholars. In response to these concerns, the Declaration of Helsinki was revised in 2000, 2008 and 2013, eventually endorsing the golden standard instead of the local standard of care. The European Union adopted a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethical Review of Health Systems Research in Low- and Middle-Income Countries: A Conceptual Exploration.Adnan A. Hyder, Abbas Rattani, Carleigh Krubiner, Abdulgafoor M. Bachani & Nhan T. Tran - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (2):28-37.
    Given that health systems research involves different aims, approaches, and methodologies as compared to more traditional clinical trials, the ethical issues present in HSR may be unique or particularly nuanced. This article outlines eight pertinent ethical issues that are particularly salient in HSR and argues that the ethical review process should be better tailored to ensure more efficient and appropriate oversight of HSR with adequate human protections, especially in low- and middle-income countries. The eight ethical areas we discuss include the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • From the Ideal Market to the Ideal Clinic: Constructing a Normative Standard of Fairness for Human Subjects Research.T. Phillips - 2011 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36 (1):79-106.
    Preventing exploitation in human subjects research requires a benchmark of fairness against which to judge the distribution of the benefits and burdens of a trial. This paper proposes the ideal market and its fair market price as a criterion of fairness. The ideal market approach is not new to discussions about exploitation, so this paper reviews Wertheimer's inchoate presentation of the ideal market as a principle of fairness, attempt of Emanuel and colleagues to apply the ideal market to human subjects (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Response to Commentators on “Rethinking Research Ethics”.Rosamond Rhodes - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):W15-W18.
    Contemporary research ethics policies started with reflection on the atrocities perpetrated upoconcentration camp inmates by Nazi doctors. Apparently, as a consequence of that experience, the policies that now guide human subject research focus on the protection of human subjects by making informed consent the centerpiece of regulatory attention. I take the choice of context for policy design, the initial prioritization of informed consent, and several associated conceptual missteps, to have set research ethics off in the wrong direction. The aim of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Questioning the Methodologic Superiority of 'Placebo' Over 'Active' Controlled Trials.Jeremy Howick - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (9):34-48.
    A resilient issue in research ethics is whether and when a placebo-controlled trial is justified if it deprives research subjects of a recognized treatment. The clinicians' moral duty to provide the best available care seems to require the use of ‘active’ controlled trials that use an established treatment as a control whenever such a therapy is available. In another regard, ACTs are supposedly methodologically inferior to PCTs. Hence, the moral duty of the clinical researcher to use the best methods will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The Duty to Register Phase I Trials.Peter T. Saunders - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (8):41-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Enhancing Informed Consent in Clinical Trials and Exploring Resistances to Disclosing Adverse Clinical Trial Results.John D. Banja & Boadie Dunlop - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (8):39-41.
    The impression one derives from the target article on “The Duty to Disclose Adverse Clinical Trials Results” is that Liao and colleagues (2009) envision a research platform consisting only of a tea...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • When argument fails.Charles Weijer - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):10 – 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • I thought we were in this together?Howard Trachtman - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):30 – 31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Therapeutic beneficence and patient recruitment in randomized controlled clinical trials.Howard Mann - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (2):35 – 36.
    (2002). Therapeutic Beneficence and Patient Recruitment in Randomized Controlled Clinical Trials. The American Journal of Bioethics: Vol. 2, No. 2, pp. 35-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Rethinking Research Ethics.Rosamond Rhodes - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (10):19-36.
    Contemporary research ethics policies started with reflection on the atrocities perpetrated upon concentration camp inmates by Nazi doctors. Apparently, as a consequence of that experience, the policies that now guide human subject research focus on the protection of human subjects by making informed consent the centerpiece of regulatory attention. I take the choice of context for policy design, the initial prioritization of informed consent, and several associated conceptual missteps, to have set research ethics off in the wrong direction. The aim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Gene by Environment Research to Prevent Externalizing Problem Behavior: Ethical Questions Raised from a Public Healthcare Perspective.Rabia R. Chhangur, Joyce Weeland, Walter Matthys & Geertjan Overbeek - 2015 - Public Health Ethics 8 (3):295-304.
    The main public health advantages of examining gene by environment interactions in externalizing behavior lie in the realm of personalized interventions. Nevertheless, the incorporation of genetic data in randomized controlled trials is fraught with difficulties and raises ethical questions. This paper has been written from the perspective of developmental psychologists who, as researchers, see themselves confronted with important and in part new kinds of ethical questions arising from G × E research in social sciences. The aim is to explicate and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A capacity-based approach for addressing ancillary care needs: implications for research in resource limited settings.Patricia L. Bright & Robert M. Nelson - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (11):672-676.
    A paediatric clinical trial conducted in a developing country is likely to encounter conditions or illnesses in participants unrelated to the study. Since local healthcare resources may be inadequate to meet these needs, research clinicians may face the dilemma of deciding when to provide ancillary care and to what extent. The authors propose a model for identifying ancillary care obligations that draws on assessments of urgency, the capacity of the local healthcare infrastructure and the capacity of the research infrastructure. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Response to Commentators on "Sham Surgery: An Ethical Analysis".Franklin G. Miller - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (4):36-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sham Surgery and Genuine Standards of Care: Can the Two be Reconciled?Alex John London & Joseph B. Kadane - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (4):61-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Privacy Overkill.Rosamond Rhodes & Daniel A. Moros - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (9):12-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sham surgery: An ethical analysis.Franklin G. Miller - 2004 - Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (1):157-166.
    Surgical clinical trials have seldom used a “sham” or placebo surgical procedure as a control, owing to ethical concerns. Recently, several ethical commentators have argued that sham surgery is either inherently or presumptively unethical. In this article I contend that these arguments are mistaken, and that there are no sound ethical reasons for an absolute prohibition of sham surgery in clinical trials. Reflecting on three cases of sham surgery, especially on the recently reported results of a sham-controlled trial of arthroscopic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Clinical Investigator as Fiduciary: Discarding a Misguided Idea.E. Haavi Morreim - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):586-598.
    One of the most important questions in the ethics of human clinical research asks what obligations investigators owe the people who enroll in their studies. Research differs in many ways from standard care - the added uncertainties, for instance, and the nontherapeutic interventions such as diagnostic tests whose only purpose is to measure the effects of the research intervention. Hence arises the question whether a physician engaged in clinical research has the same obligations toward research subjects that he owes his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Sham Surgery: An Ethical Analysis.Franklin G. Miller - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (4):41-48.
    Surgical clinical trials have seldom used a "sham" or placebo surgical procedure as a control, owing to ethical concerns. Recently, several ethical commentators have argued that sham surgery is either inherently or presumptively unethical. In this article I contend that these arguments are mistaken and that there are no sound ethical reasons for an absolute prohibition of sham surgery in clinical trials. Reflecting on three cases of sham surgery, especially on the recently reported results of a sham-controlled trial of arthroscopic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Sham surgery: Not an oxymoron.Charles J. Kowalski - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (4):8 – 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Accountability and pediatric physician-researchers: are theoretical models compatible with Canadian lived experience?Christine Czoli, Michael Da Silva, Randi Zlotnik Shaul, Lori D'Agincourt-Canning, Christy Simpson, Katherine Boydell, Natalie Rashkovan & Sharon Vanin - 2011 - Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 6:15.
    Physician-researchers are bound by professional obligations stemming from both the role of the physician and the role of the researcher. Currently, the dominant models for understanding the relationship between physician-researchers' clinical duties and research duties fit into three categories: the similarity position, the difference position and the middle ground. The law may be said to offer a fourth.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Splitting the Difference Position.Abraham P. Schwab - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (4):74-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Clinical Investigator as Fiduciary: Discarding a Misguided Idea.E. Haavi Morreim - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):586-598.
    One of the most important questions in the ethics of human clinical research asks what obligations investigators owe the people who enroll in their studies. Research differs in many ways from standard care - the added uncertainties, for instance, and the nontherapeutic interventions such as diagnostic tests whose only purpose is to measure the effects of the research intervention. Hence arises the question whether a physician engaged in clinical research has the same obligations toward research subjects that he owes his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations