Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Kuhn’s “wrong turning” and legacy today.Yafeng Shan - 2020 - Synthese 197 (1):381-406.
    Alexander Bird indicates that the significance of Thomas Kuhn in the history of philosophy of science is somehow paradoxical. On the one hand, Kuhn was one of the most influential and important philosophers of science in the second half of the twentieth century. On the other hand, nowadays there is little distinctively Kuhn’s legacy in the sense that most of Kuhn’s work has no longer any philosophical significance. Bird argues that the explanation of the paradox of Kuhn’s legacy is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Mendel’s use of mathematical modelling: ratios, predictions and the appeal to tradition.Amir Teicher - 2014 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 36 (2):187-208.
    The seventh section of Gregor Mendel’s famous 1866 paper contained a peculiar mathematical model, which predicted the expected ratios between the number of constant and hybrid types, assuming self-pollination continued throughout further generations. This model was significant for Mendel’s argumentation and was perceived as inseparable from his entire theory at the time. A close examination of this model reveals that it has several perplexing aspects which have not yet been systematically scrutinized. The paper analyzes those aspects, dispels some common misconceptions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genetic “information” or the indomitability of a persisting scientific metaphor.Tareq Syed, Michael Bölker & Mathias Gutmann - 2008 - Poiesis and Praxis 5 (3-4):193-209.
    In the history of genetics, the information-theoretical description of the gene, beginning in the early 1960s, had a significant effect on the concept of the gene. Information is a highly complex metaphor which is applicable in view of the description of substances, processes, and spatio-temporal organisation. Thus, information can be understood as a functional particle of many different language games (some of them belonging to subdisciplines of genetics, as the biochemical language game, some of them belonging to linguistics and informatics). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mendel in the Modern Classroom.Mike U. Smith & Niklas M. Gericke - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (1-2):151-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • More than a Mentor: Leonard Darwin’s Contribution to the Assimilation of Mendelism into Eugenics and Darwinism.Norberto Serpente - 2016 - Journal of the History of Biology 49 (3):461-494.
    This article discusses the contribution to evolutionary theory of Leonard Darwin, the eighth child of Charles Darwin. By analysing the correspondence Leonard Darwin maintained with Ronald Aylmer Fisher in conjunction with an assessment of his books and other written works between the 1910s and 1930s, this article argues for a more prominent role played by him than the previously recognised in the literature as an informal mentor of Fisher. The paper discusses Leonard’s efforts to amalgamate Mendelism with both Eugenics and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The real objective of Mendel's paper: A response to Falk and Sarkar's criticism. [REVIEW]Floyd V. Monaghan & Alain F. Corcos - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (1):95-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mendel and the Path to Genetics: Portraying Science as a Social Process.Kostas Kampourakis - 2013 - Science & Education 22 (2):293-324.
    Textbook descriptions of the foundations of Genetics give the impression that besides Mendel’s no other research on heredity took place during the nineteenth century. However, the publication of the Origin of Species in 1859, and the criticism that it received, placed the study of heredity at the centre of biological thought. Consequently, Herbert Spencer, Charles Darwin himself, Francis Galton, William Keith Brooks, Carl von Nägeli, August Weismann, and Hugo de Vries attempted to develop theories of heredity under an evolutionary perspective, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The rise and fall of dominance.Raphael Falk - 2001 - Biology and Philosophy 16 (3):285-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The real objective of Mendel's paper: A response to Monaghan and Corcos. [REVIEW]Raphael Falk & Sahotra Sarkar - 1991 - Biology and Philosophy 6 (4):447-451.
    Mendel's work in hybridization is ipso facto a study in inheritance. He is explicit in his interest to formulate universal generalizations, and at least in the case of the independent segregation of traits, he formulated his conclusions in the form of a law. Mendel did not discern, however, the inheritance of traits from that of the potential for traits. Choosing to study discrete non-overlapping traits, this did not hamper his efforts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Mendel in Genetics Teaching: Some Contributions from History of Science and Articles for Teachers.Charbel N. El-Hani - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (1-2):173-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mendel's experiments: A reinterpretation. [REVIEW]Federico Di Trocchio - 1991 - Journal of the History of Biology 24 (3):485-519.
    My conclusion is that Mendel deliberately, though without any real falsification, tried to suggest to his audience and readers an unlikely and substantially wrong reconstruction of the first and most important phase of his research. In my book I offer many reasons for this strange and surprising behavior,53 but the main argument rests on the fact of linkage. Mendelian genetics cannot account for linkage because it was based on the idea of applying probability theory to the problem of species evolution. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Special Issue: Philosophical Considerations in the Teaching of Biology. Part II, Evolution, Development and Genetics.Kostas Kampourakis (ed.) - 2013 - Springer (Science & Education).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scientific myth‐conceptions.Douglas Allchin - 2003 - Science Education 87 (3):329-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Gregor Mendel and “myth‐conceptions”.Julie Westerlund & Daniel Fairbanks - 2004 - Science Education 88 (5):754-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Exemplarising the Origin of Genetics: A Path to Genetics (From Mendel to Bateson).Yafeng Shan - 2016 - Dissertation, University College London
    This thesis aims to propose and defend a new way of analysing and understanding the origin of genetics (from Mendel to Bateson). Traditionally philosophers used to analyse the history of genetics in terms of theories. However, I will argue that this theory-based approach is highly problematic. In Chapter 1, I shall critically review the theory-driven approach to analysisng the history of genetics and diagnose its problems. In Chapter 2, inspired by Kuhn’s concept “exemplar”, I shall make a new interpretation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lawson's Shoehorn, or Should the Philosophy of Science Be Rated 'X'?Douglas Allchin - 2003 - Science & Education 12 (3):315-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations