Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Aenesidemus and the Academy.Fernanda Decleva Caizzi - 1992 - Classical Quarterly 42 (01):176-.
    In cod. 212 of his Bibliotheca, Photius provides some information of great importance for our scanty knowledge of Pyrrhonian scepticism between Timon and Sextus.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotle and the Stoics on the Notion of ἐνέργεια.Giuseppe Nastasi - 2024 - Apeiron 57 (4):553-582.
    The Stoic theory of movement has never been the object of a deep investigation despite the considerable number of sources in Neoplatonist commentators. This paper explores for the first time the Stoic notion of ἐνέργεια, which plays a fundamental role in the Stoic conception of movement and generally in the characterization of interaction between bodies. I will show that the Stoics identified movement and activity, so that everything that is active is necessarily moved. This implies that the Stoics merely characterized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is Pythagorean in the Pseudo-Pythagorean Literature?Leonid Zhmud - 2019 - Philologus: Zeitschrift für Antike Literatur Und Ihre Rezeption 163 (1):72-94.
    This paper discusses continuity between ancient Pythagoreanism and the pseudo-Pythagorean writings, which began to appear after the end of the Pythagorean school ca. 350 BC. Relying on a combination of temporal, formal and substantial criteria, I divide Pseudopythagorica into three categories: 1) early Hellenistic writings ascribed to Pythagoras and his family members; 2) philosophical treatises written mostly, yet not exclusively, in pseudo-Doric from the turn of the first century BC under the names of real or fictional Pythagoreans; 3) writings attributed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A Relative Improvement.Tad Brennan & Jongsuh James Lee - 2014 - Phronesis 59 (3):246-271.
    The Mode of Relativity in Agrippa’s Five Modes does not fit with the other four modes, and disrupts an otherwise elegant system. We argue that it is not the familiar argument from epistemic relativism, but a formal condition on the structure of justifications: the principle that epistemic grounding relations cannot be reflexive. This understanding of Agrippan Relativity leads to a better understanding of the Modes of Hypothesis and Reciprocity, a clearer outline of the structure of Agrippa’s system as a whole, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Clement of Alexandria on Aristotle's (Cosmo-)Theology (Clem. Protrept. 5.66.4).A. P. Bos - 1993 - Classical Quarterly 43 (01):177-.
    In this paper I will reconsider the doxographical text about Aristotle in Clement of Alexandria's Protrepticus 5.66.4: οδν δ ομαι χαλεπν νταθα γενμενος κα τν κ το Περιπτου μνησθναι· κα γε τς αρσεως πατρ, τν λων ο νοσας τν πατρα, τν καλομενον ‘πατον’ ψυχν εναι το πντος οεται· τουτστι το κσμου τν ψυχν θεν πολαμβνων ατς ατ περιπερεται. γρ τοι μχρι τς σελνης ατς διορζων τν πρνοιαν, πειτα τν κσμον θεν γομενος περιτρπεται, τν μοιρον θεο θεν δογματζων.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La théorie de la vision chez Galien : la colonne qui saute et autres énigmes.Heinrich Von Staden - 2012 - Philosophie Antique 12:115-155.
    Du point de vue méthodologique et épistémologique, la vision occupe une place privilégiée dans les œuvres de Galien de Pergame, ce qui explique les tentatives répétées de ce dernier pour en expliquer le fonctionnement. En partie grâce à la dissection et à la vivisection pratiquées sur des animaux de différentes espèces, il développa une connaissance détaillée de l’anatomie de l’œil, du nerf optique, du cerveau, des muscles oculaires et du système vasculaire cérébral et oculaire. Il utilisa avec habileté cet impressionnant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Levels of explanation in Galen.P. N. Singe - 1997 - Classical Quarterly 47 (02):525-.
    Galen's æuvre presents a remarkably varied body of texts–varied in subject matter, style, and didactic purpose. Logical tracts sit alongside tomes of drug–lore; handbooks of dietetics alongside anatomical investigations; treatises of physiology alongside ethical opuscula. These differences in type have received some, though as yet insufficient, scholarly attention. Mario Vegetti demonstrated the coexistence of two ‘profili’ or images of the art of medicine: Galen presents the art as an Aristotelian deductive science, on the one hand, and as a technician's craft, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristote et la signification.David Sedley - 2004 - Philosophie Antique 4 (4):5-25.
    Aristotle says at the start of the De interpretatione that words symbolise thoughts, which are in turn likenesses of things. The present paper argues that he is speaking here primarily of the signification of whole sentences, and at most secondarily of the semantics of individual words. This proposal is defended by drawing attention to a shift in the meaning of ‘sign’ and cognate terms that occurs in the course of the first chapter, one which enables us to separate the way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The naming of Thrasyllus in Apuleius' Metamorphoses1.I. D. Repath - 2000 - Classical Quarterly 50 (02):627-.
    It is usually assumed that Apuleius gave one of his characters the name ‘Thrasyllus’ because of its etymological connection with θρασ. Indeed it is singularly appropriate and Apuleius himself draws attention to the fact: Thrasyllus, praeceps alioquin et de ipso nomine temerarius… . However, it does not follow that a name with such an etymological significance can have no other connotations: in this note I suggest that there is a further frame of reference behind ‘Thrasyllus’ and that Apuleius may have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Alexander of Aphrodisias : a source of Origen’s philosophy?Ilaria Ramelli - 2014 - Philosophie Antique 14:237-289.
    Alexandre d’Aphrodise et Origène sont deux philosophes et professeurs de philosophie semi-contemporains qui composaient le même genre d’œuvres. Origène était un philosophe chrétien, ancien élève d’Ammonius Saccas, le maître de Plotin. Il est très probable qu’Origène connaissait les écrits d’Alexandre d’Aphrodise, qui étaient lus à l’école de Plotin, et fut inspiré par eux. Beaucoup d’éléments soutiennent ma thèse. Par exemple, le Traité des Principes d’Origène dans sa structure est probablement emprunté à l’œuvre homonyme d’Alexandre d’Aphrodise ; l’expression ἦν ποτε ὅτε (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stoici e Peripatetici su agire, patire e movimento: la testimonianza di Simplicio.Giuseppe Nastasi - 2023 - Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 44 (2):333-365.
    Simplicius’ Commentary on Aristotle’s Categories contains the most extended testimony about the Stoic conception of acting (ποιεῖν) and undergoing (πάσχειν). Simplicius ascribed to the Stoics the idea that acting and undergoing are to be reduced to the movement. To this opinion Simplicius opposed the Aristotelian view according to which acting and undergoing are two different categories. In this paper I intend to outline the original Stoic position comparing the reportage of Simplicius with other Stoic sources. Later, I will deal with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Armonizar a Pirrón y Enesidemo Sobre una línea problemática de Aristocles y su contexto.Alfonso Correa Motta - 2023 - Ideas Y Valores 72.
    En este artículo argumento en contra de una intervención textual, sugerida por Moraux y adoptada por Chiesara, a una línea del tratado de Aristocles sobre la filosofía pirrónica. Esta lectura conservadora me permite resaltar la importancia del contexto en el que se inserta la línea en disputa. Pienso que el pasaje es crucial para la crítica de Aristocles a los escépticos, pues implica un intento consciente, aunque implícito, por unificar dos corrientes distintas del pirronismo: la original, representada por la apropiación (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Éphrem, Bardesane et Albinus sur les incorporels.Izabela Jurasz - 2017 - Philosophie Antique 17:169-204.
    Le Discours contre le Discours « De Domnus » rend compte d’un triple débat, dans lequel trois personnages interviennent sur la question des « incorporels », point difficile de la doctrine stoïcienne. La polémique rédigée par le stoïcien Bardesane, en réaction aux positions du platonicien Albinus, a été examinée par Éphrem le Syrien, chrétien et polémiste antibardesanite. Il est l’auteur du Discours et notre seule source d’information sur cette controverse. Or, la manière dont Éphrem aborde la question litigieuse est spontanément (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Body and Cosmos in Galen’s Account of the Soul.Matyáš Havrda - 2017 - Phronesis 62 (1):69-89.
    _ Source: _Volume 62, Issue 1, pp 69 - 89 Galen’s physiology—his theory of elements, mixtures and the emergence of natural capacities—compels him to conceive of each part of the soul as a peculiar mixture of elementary qualities in the material substance of the organ in which it is located. The reason why Galen, nevertheless, refrains from making a dogmatic assertion about the substance of the soul, or of human nature in general, is the acknowledged failure to account for two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle as an Astronomer? Sosigenes’ Account of Metaphysics Λ.8.Pantelis Golitsis - 2023 - Rhizomata 11 (1):126-137.
    I have argued elsewhere that the idea that Aristotle aspired to improve the theories of the planetary motions of Eudoxus and Callippus by adding the ‘counteracting’ spheres (ἀνελίττουσαι) first emerged with the Peripatetic exegete Sosigenes in the second century CE. This paper supplements that argument by contrasting two major lines of interpretation of the astronomical system set out in Metaphysics Λ.8: Adrastus of Aphrodisias’ widely ahistorical account, and Sosigenes’ attempt to save Aristotle against later developments of astronomical science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fire and heat: Yaḥyā B. ʿadī and avicenna on the essentiality of being substance or accident.Fedor Benevich - 2017 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 27 (2):237-267.
    Avicenna's analysis of the definition of substance and accident repeatedly emphasizes two points: one and the same essence cannot be substance in one instance and accident in another; whetherxis extrinsic or intrinsic for an underlying subject,ydoes not tell us anything as to whetherxis substance or not. Both points are development in an argument against certain unnamed people who claimed the opposite. In this article I will show that Avicenna's opponents are to be identified with the mainstream Baghdad Peripatetic School which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations