Switch to: References

Citations of:

Abstract Measurement Theory

Synthese 76 (1):179-182 (1988)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. How to Read a Representor.Edward Elliott - forthcoming - Ergo.
    Imprecise probabilities are often modelled with representors, or sets of probability functions. In the recent literature, two ways of interpreting representors have emerged as especially prominent: vagueness interpretations, according to which each probability function in the set represents how the agent's beliefs would be if any vagueness were precisified away; and comparativist interpretations, according to which the set represents those comparative confidence relations that are common to all probability functions therein. I argue that these interpretations have some important limitations. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Measurement‐Theoretic Accounts of Propositional Attitudes. [REVIEW]Robert J. Matthews - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (11):828-841.
    In the late 1970s and early 1980s a number of philosophers, notably Churchland, Field, Stalnaker, Dennett, and Davidson, began to argue that propositional attitude predicates (such as believes that it’s sunny outside) are a species of measure predicate, analogous in important ways to numerical predicates by which we attribute physical magnitudes (such as mass, length, and temperature). Other philosophers, including myself, have subsequently developed the idea in greater detail. In this paper I sketch the general outlines of measurement‐theoretic accounts of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Divergent Mathematical Treatments in Utility Theory.Davide Rizza - 2016 - Erkenntnis 81 (6):1287-1303.
    In this paper I study how divergent mathematical treatments affect mathematical modelling, with a special focus on utility theory. In particular I examine recent work on the ranking of information states and the discounting of future utilities, in order to show how, by replacing the standard analytical treatment of the models involved with one based on the framework of Nonstandard Analysis, diametrically opposite results are obtained. In both cases, the choice between the standard and nonstandard treatment amounts to a selection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Are the power exponents of magnitude estimation functions too high?George A. Gescheider - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):275-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconciling Fechner and Stevens: Toward a unified psychophysical law.Lester E. Krueger - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):251-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Additive representation of separable preferences over infinite products.Marcus Pivato - 2014 - Theory and Decision 77 (1):31-83.
    Let X\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\mathcal{X }$$\end{document} be a set of outcomes, and let I\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\mathcal{I }$$\end{document} be an infinite indexing set. This paper shows that any separable, permutation-invariant preference order \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$$$\end{document} on XI\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\mathcal{X }^\mathcal{I }$$\end{document} admits an additive representation. That is: there exists a linearly ordered abelian group R\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Expected utility from additive utility on semigroups.Juan C. Candeal, Juan R. de Miguel & Esteban Induráin - 2002 - Theory and Decision 53 (1):87-94.
    In the present paper we study the framework of additive utility theory, obtaining new results derived from a concurrence of algebraic and topological techniques. Such techniques lean on the concept of a connected topological totally ordered semigroup. We achieve a general result concerning the existence of continuous and additive utility functions on completely preordered sets endowed with a binary operation ``+'', not necessarily being commutative or associative. In the final part of the paper we get some applications to expected utility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extending Hartry field's instrumental account of applied mathematics to statistical mechanics.Glen Meyer - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (3):273-312.
    A serious flaw in Hartry Field’s instrumental account of applied mathematics, namely that Field must overestimate the extent to which many of the structures of our mathematical theories are reflected in the physical world, underlies much of the criticism of this account. After reviewing some of this criticism, I illustrate through an examination of the prospects for extending Field’s account to classical equilibrium statistical mechanics how this flaw will prevent any significant extension of this account beyond field theories. I note (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Numbers as quantitative relations and the traditional theory of measurement.Joel Michell - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2):389-406.
    The thesis that numbers are ratios of quantities has recently been advanced by a number of philosophers. While adequate as a definition of the natural numbers, it is not clear that this view suffices for our understanding of the reals. These require continuous quantity and relative to any such quantity an infinite number of additive relations exist. Hence, for any two magnitudes of a continuous quantity there exists no unique ratio. This problem is overcome by defining ratios, and hence real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Measurement perspective, process, and the pandemic.Vadim Keyser & Hannah Howland - 2020 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (1):1-26.
    This discussion centers on two desiderata: the role of measurement in information-gathering and physical interaction in scientific practice. By taking inspiration from van Fraassen’s view, we present a methodological account of perspectival measurement that addresses empirical practice where there is complex intervention, disagreeing results, and limited theory. The specific aim of our account is to provide a methodological prescription for developing measurement processes in the context of limited theory. The account should be useful to philosophers of science, who are interested (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Experimental effects and causal representations.Vadim Keyser - 2017 - Synthese:1-32.
    In experimental settings, scientists often “make” new things, in which case the aim is to intervene in order to produce experimental objects and processes—characterized as ‘effects’. In this discussion, I illuminate an important performative function in measurement and experimentation in general: intervention-based experimental production (IEP). I argue that even though the goal of IEP is the production of new effects, it can be informative for causal details in scientific representations. Specifically, IEP can be informative about causal relations in: regularities under (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Beyond the metrological viewpoint.Jean Baccelli - 2020 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 1:56-61.
    The representational theory of measurement has long been the central paradigm in the philosophy of measurement. Such is not the case anymore, partly under the influence of the critique according to which RTM offers too poor descriptions of the measurement procedures actually followed in science. This can be called the metrological critique of RTM. I claim that the critique is partly irrelevant. This is because, in general, RTM is not in the business of describing measurement procedures, be it in idealized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Measurement in Carnap's late Philosophy of Science.Vadim Batitsky - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (2):87-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Unity and diversity of neurelectric and psychophysical functions: The invariance question.Gerald S. Wasserman & Lolin T. Wang-Bennett - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):297-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • On the origin and function of the psychophysical transformation.Roger N. Shepard - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):290-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jnds and ROCs.Donald D. Dorfman - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):273-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Higher Values and Non-Archimedean Additivity.Erik Carlson - 2007 - Theoria 73 (1):3-27.
    Many philosophers have claimed that extensive or additive measurement is incompatible with the existence of "higher values", any amount of which is better than any amount of some other value. In this paper, it is shown that higher values can be incorporated in a non-standard model of extensive measurement, with values represented by sets of ordered pairs of real numbers, rather than by single reals. The suggested model is mathematically fairly simple, and it applies to structures including negative as well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Some measurement-theoretic concerns about Hale's ‘reals by abstraction';.Vadim Batitsky - 2002 - Philosophia Mathematica 10 (3):286-303.
    Hale proposes a neo-logicist definition of real numbers by abstraction as ratios defined on a complete ordered domain of quantities (magnitudes). I argue that Hale's definition faces insuperable epistemological and ontological difficulties. On the epistemological side, Hale is committed to an explanation of measurement applications of reals which conflicts with several theorems in measurement theory. On the ontological side, Hale commits himself to the necessary and a priori existence of at least one complete ordered domain of quantities, which is extremely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Foundations of applied mathematics I.Jeffrey Ketland - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):4151-4193.
    This paper aims to study the foundations of applied mathematics, using a formalized base theory for applied mathematics: ZFCAσ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$ \mathsf {ZFCA}_{\sigma }$$\end{document} with atoms, where the subscript used refers to a signature specific to the application. Examples are given, illustrating the following five features of applied mathematics: comprehension principles, application conditionals, representation hypotheses, transfer principles and abstract equivalents.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Magnitude scales, category scales, and number scales.Stanley J. Rule - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):288-288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • G and S go fishing.Lawrence E. Marks - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):282-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unifying psychophysics: And what if things are not so simple?Marc Brysbaert & Géry D'Ydewalle - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):271-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Is a unified psychophysical law realistic?Jüri Allik - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):267-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • The Analytic Versus Representational Theory of Measurement: A Philosophy of Science Perspective.Zoltan Domotor & Vadim Batitsky - 2008 - Measurement Science Review 8 (6):129-146.
    In this paper we motivate and develop the analytic theory of measurement, in which autonomously specified algebras of quantities (together with the resources of mathematical analysis) are used as a unified mathematical framework for modeling (a) the time-dependent behavior of natural systems, (b) interactions between natural systems and measuring instruments, (c) error and uncertainty in measurement, and (d) the formal propositional language for describing and reasoning about measurement results. We also discuss how a celebrated theorem in analysis, known as Gelfand (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Extensive measurement and ratio functions.Brent Mundy - 1988 - Synthese 75 (1):1 - 23.
    Extensive measurement theory is developed in terms of theratio of two elements of an arbitrary (not necessarily Archimedean) extensive structure; thisextensive ratio space is a special case of a more general structure called aratio space. Ratio spaces possess a natural family of numerical scales (r-scales) which are definable in non-representational terms; ther-scales for an extensive ratio space thus constitute a family of numerical scales (extensive r-scales) for extensive structures which are defined in a non-representational manner. This is interpreted as involving (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Faithful representation, physical extensive measurement theory and archimedean axioms.Brent Mundy - 1987 - Synthese 70 (3):373 - 400.
    The formal methods of the representational theory of measurement (RTM) are applied to the extensive scales of physical science, with some modifications of interpretation and of formalism. The interpretative modification is in the direction of theoretical realism rather than the narrow empiricism which is characteristic of RTM. The formal issues concern the formal representational conditions which extensive scales should be assumed to satisfy; I argue in the physical case for conditions related to weak rather than strong extensive measurement, in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Sensory magnitudes and their physical correlates.Richard M. Warren - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):296-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conjuring Fechner's spirit.Eckart Scheerer - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):288-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Nineteenth-century attempts to decide between psychophysical laws.David J. Murray - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):284-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Strict Finitism, Feasibility, and the Sorites.Walter Dean - 2018 - Review of Symbolic Logic 11 (2):295-346.
    This article bears on four topics: observational predicates and phenomenal properties, vagueness, strict finitism as a philosophy of mathematics, and the analysis of feasible computability. It is argued that reactions to strict finitism point towards a semantics for vague predicates in the form of nonstandard models of weak arithmetical theories of the sort originally introduced to characterize the notion of feasibility as understood in computational complexity theory. The approach described eschews the use of nonclassical logic and related devices like degrees (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Fantasies in psychophysical scaling: Do category estimates reflect the true psychophysical scale?Mark Wagner - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):294-295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To resolve Fechner versus Stevens: Settle the dispute concerning “ratios” and “differences”.Michael H. Birnbaum - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):270-271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An epistemological use of nonstandard analysis to answer Zeno's objections against motion.William I. McLaughlin & Sylvia L. Miller - 1992 - Synthese 92 (3):371 - 384.
    Three of Zeno's objections to motion are answered by utilizing a version of nonstandard analysis, internal set theory, interpreted within an empirical context. Two of the objections are without force because they rely upon infinite sets, which always contain nonstandard real numbers. These numbers are devoid of numerical meaning, and thus one cannot render the judgment that an object is, in fact, located at a point in spacetime for which they would serve as coordinates. The third objection, an arrow never (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A realistic look at Putnam's argument against realism.Vadim Batitsky - 2000 - Foundations of Science 5 (3):299-321.
    Putnam's ``model-theoretic'' argument against metaphysical realism presupposes that an ideal scientific theory is expressible in a first order language. The central aim of this paper is to show that Putnam's ``first orderization'' of science, although unchallenged by numerous critics, makes his argument unsound even for adequate theories, never mind an ideal one. To this end, I will argue that quantitative theories, which dominate the natural sciences, can be adequately interpreted and evaluated only with the help of so-called theories of measurement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unified psychophysics: Wouldn't it be loverly….Robert Teghtsoonian & Martha Teghtsoonian - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):292-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychophysical law: Some doubts about unification.Scott Parker - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):286-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On various ways of establishing a psychophysical function empirically.Josef Lukas - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):281-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychophysical law: The need for more than one level of explanation.Hans-Georg Geissler - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):274-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Experimental evidence for Fechner's and Stevens's laws.Donald Laming - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):277-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Experimental effects and causal representations.Vadim Keyser - 2017 - Synthese 198 (S21):5145-5176.
    In experimental settings, scientists often “make” new things, in which case the aim is to intervene in order to produce experimental objects and processes—characterized as ‘effects’. In this discussion, I illuminate an important performative function in measurement and experimentation in general: intervention-based experimental production. I argue that even though the goal of IEP is the production of new effects, it can be informative for causal details in scientific representations. Specifically, IEP can be informative about causal relations in: regularities under study; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Discovery of empirical theories based on the measurement theory.E. E. Vityaev & B. Y. Kovalerchuk - 2004 - Minds and Machines 14 (4):551-573.
    The purpose of this work is to analyse the cognitive process of the domain theories in terms of the measurement theory to develop a computational machine learning approach for implementing it. As a result, the relational data mining approach, the authors proposed in the preceding books, was improved. We present the approach as an implementation of the cognitive process as the measurement theory perceived. We analyse the cognitive process in the first part of the paper and present the theory and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Measuring the hedonimeter.Brian Skyrms & Louis Narens - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (12):3199-3210.
    We revisit classical Utilitarianism by connecting and generalizing two ideas. The first is that there is a representation theorem possible for hedonic value similar to, but also importantly different from, the one provided by von Neumann and Morgenstern to measure decision utility. The idea is to use objective time, in place of objective chance, to measure hedonic value. This representation for hedonic value delivers a stronger kind of scale than von Neumann–Morgenstern utility, a ratio scale rather than merely an interval (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Elusive Case for Relationalism about the Attitudes: Reply to Rattan.Robert J. Matthews - 2017 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 94 (2):453-462.
    The question I address here is whether there is anything about what Rattan describes as the normative and perspectival aspects of propositional attitudes that demands a relational account of the attitudes, specifically anything that cannot equally well be explained on measurement-theoretic accounts of the sort that I (and others) have defended which do not incorporate or presume a cognitive relation to a proposition. I argue that there is not.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Integration psychophysics.Norman H. Anderson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):268-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Psychophysics and metaphysics.David J. Weiss - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):298-299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Option 4: Forswear the psychophysical law.Lawrence M. Ward - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):295-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensory scaling: Unanswered questions.Michel Treisman - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):293-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Psychophysics: On the possibility of another approach.Tarow Indow - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):276-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Is there really only one representation for stimulus intensity?Bruce Schneider - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):290-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Anger In-the-Social-Order.Albert B. Robillard - 1996 - Body and Society 2 (1):17-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations