Switch to: References

Citations of:

Werke [Book Review]

Leipzig,: A. Kröner. Edited by August Messer (1930)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Personal Identity and Self-Interpretation & Natural Right and Natural Emotions.Gabor Boros, Judit Szalai & Oliver Toth (eds.) - 2020 - Budapest: Eötvös University Press.
    Collection of papers presented at the 2nd and 3rd Budapest Seminar in Early Modern Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Faces in the Clouds: A New Theory of Religion.Stewart Guthrie - 1993 - New York and Oxford: Oup Usa.
    Guthrie contends that religion can best be understood as systematic anthropomorphism - the attribution of human characteristics to nonhuman things and events. Religion, he says, consists of seeing the world as human like. He offers a fascinating array of examples to show how this strategy pervades secular life and how it characterizes religious experience.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   162 citations  
  • Nietzsche's and Pessoa's Psychological Fictionalism.Pietro Gori & Antonio Cardiello - 2016 - Pessoa Plural 10:578-605.
    In a note to G.R.S. Mead’s "Quests Old and New", where he found a section devoted to Hans Vaihinger’s main ideas, Fernando Pessoa reflects on the consequences of the fictionalist approach to both our perception of the I and the value of consciousness. These questions correspond to some statements that we find in Nietzsche’s writings, which in particular Vaihinger refers to in his Die Philosophie des Als-ob. Our aim is thus to compare Nietzsche’s and Pessoa’s view of the I and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theological Shamelessness? A Response to Arthur Peacocke and David A. Pailin.Vítor Westhelle - 2000 - Zygon 35 (1):165-172.
    This is a theological response to two programmatic essays, “Science and the Future of Theology: Critical Issues,” by Arthur Peacocke and “What Game is Being Played? The Need for Clarity about theRelationship between Scientific and Theological Understanding,” by David A. Pailin. It argues that the two authors, well informed by the recent developments in science, are reduplicating some methodological and epistemological trends common to nineteenth‐century theology. The feasibility of their project should, therefore, be examined on whether they succeed in answering (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Consciousness as a topic of investigation in Western thought.Anderson Weekes - 2010 - In Michel Weber & Anderson Weekes (eds.), Process Approaches to Consciousness in Psychology, Neuroscience, and Philosophy of Mind. Albany: State University of New York Press. pp. 73-136.
    Terms for consciousness, used with a cognitive meaning, emerged as count nouns in the 17th century. This transformation repeats an evolution that had taken place in late antiquity, when related vocabulary, used in the sense of conscience, went from being mass nouns designating states to count nouns designating faculties possessed by every individual. The reified concept of consciousness resulted from the rejection of the Scholastic-Aristotelian theory of mind according to which the mind is not a countable thing, but a pure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anti-foundationalist Practices of Truth. Foucault, Nietzsche, and James.Pietro Gori - 2024 - In Pietro Gori & Lorenzo Serini (eds.), Practices of truth in philosophy: historical and comparative perspectives. New York, NY: Routledge.
    The chapter explores comparatively the attention to the practical dimension that—each in his own way—Michel Foucault, Friedrich Nietzsche, and the classic pragmatist thinker William James pay when confronted with the challenge of providing a non-skeptical response to the relativist stance on truth that arose in the post-Kantian age. Particular focus will be given to the extent to which these three authors conceived of the practical framework as the only one that allows us to meaningfully address and determine truth.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Dialectic of Perspectivism I.James Conant - 2006 - SATS 7 (1):5-50.
    Philosophers ... always demand that we should think of an eye that is completely unthinkable, an eye turned in no particular direction, in which the active and interpreting forces, through which alone seeing becomes seeing something, are supposed to be lacking; they always demand of the eye an absurdity and a nonsense.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • National socialism and the disintegration of values: Reflections on Nietzsche, Rosenberg, and broch. [REVIEW]Mark W. Roche - 1992 - Journal of Value Inquiry 26 (3):367-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Dialectic of Perspectivism, II.James Conant - 2006 - SATS 7 (1):6-57.
    As we have seen, the crucial step in Nietzsche’s argument for his early doctrine is summed by in the following remark: ‘If we are forced to comprehend all things only under these forms, then it ceases to be amazing that in all things we actually comprehend nothing but these forms’ (1979, pp. 87–8). Before eventually learning to be suspicious of it, Nietzsche spends a good deal of time wondering instead what it would mean to live with the conclusion that (what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kontinentales erbe und analytische methode. Nelson Goodman und die tradition.Gottfried Gabriel - 2000 - Erkenntnis 52 (2):185-198.
    Goodman's most important contribution to philosophy seems to be his analysis of the relation between facts of science and fictions of art. His view can be seen as a kind of complementary pluralism. That is to say, science and art are two complementary forms of achieving cognition. This position overcame the positivistic view (of his teacher Carnap) according to which the value of art is restricted to the non-cognitive function of expressing emotions. In this paper I compare some of Goodman's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conversion in philosophy: Wittgenstein's "saving word".Antonia Soulez & Melissa McMahon - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    : Wittgenstein raises the notion of "conversion" in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical "grammar," in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries (Freud, James) and from the history of philosophy (Saint Augustine, Descartes).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Embarkation for Abdera: Historicization in Nietzsche’s Second Untimely Meditation.Henning Trüper - 2022 - Quaderns de Filosofia 9 (1):55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Style as a Historical Category.Michael Otte - 1991 - Science in Context 4 (2):233-264.
    The ArgumentIn writing the history of science, the fluctuations between two meanings of the concept of style are of special interest: a simple or direct meaning of this concept referring to a means of expression and of presentation, and a philosophical interpretation of this term referring to “a world of objective spiritual order.” The last two chapters of this paper consider the perspective of the simple meaning of the concept, the first two chapters take the philosophical meaning as their starting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nietzsche's Fourfold Conception of the Self.Robert Miner - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (4):337-360.
    Abstract Struck by essentialist and anti-essentialist elements in his writings, Nietzsche's readers have wondered whether his conception of the self is incoherent or paradoxical. This paper demonstrates that his conception of the self, while complex, is not paradoxical or incoherent, but contains four distinct levels. Section I shows Schopenhauer as Educator to contain an early description of the four levels: (1) a person's deepest self, embracing all that cannot be educated or molded; (2) a person's ego; (3) a person's ?ideal? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Foucault historien et “historien ” du présent.J. N. Kaufmann - 1986 - Dialogue 25 (2):223-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's “Saving Word”.Antonia Soulez - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of “conversion” in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical “grammar,” in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Barely visible: Heidegger’s Platonic Theology.Andrzej Serafin - 2021 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 26 (2):227-241.
    Heidegger’s thinking, according to his own testimony, is rooted in two traditions of philosophy: Platonic-Aristotelian ontology and Husserl’s phe­nomenology. Heidegger’s claim that the original understanding of Being is lost and has to be rediscovered conjoins the phenomenological claim that there is a certain mode of seeing that enables a revelatory philosophical insight. I would like to show how Heidegger combines both these claims in his supposition that the original philosophical conceptuality, as developed by Plato and Aristotle, was lost but can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark